/
Nature, Aesthetic Judgment and Objectivity Nature, Aesthetic Judgment and Objectivity

Nature, Aesthetic Judgment and Objectivity - PowerPoint Presentation

faustina-dinatale
faustina-dinatale . @faustina-dinatale
Follow
386 views
Uploaded On 2017-03-16

Nature, Aesthetic Judgment and Objectivity - PPT Presentation

From Aesthetics and the Environment Allen Carlson Notes by Shannon Maylath Nature and Objectivity Opposition to the view that some aesthetic judgments are objective fall into one of two camps ID: 524859

aesthetic nature judgments art nature aesthetic art judgments natural correct category psychological categories standard properties perceptual work carlson perceived

Share:

Link:

Embed:

Download Presentation from below link

Download Presentation The PPT/PDF document "Nature, Aesthetic Judgment and Objectivi..." is the property of its rightful owner. Permission is granted to download and print the materials on this web site for personal, non-commercial use only, and to display it on your personal computer provided you do not modify the materials and that you retain all copyright notices contained in the materials. By downloading content from our website, you accept the terms of this agreement.


Presentation Transcript

Slide1

Nature, Aesthetic Judgment and Objectivity

From

Aesthetics and the Environment

Allen Carlson

Notes by Shannon MaylathSlide2

Nature and Objectivity

Opposition to the view that (some) aesthetic judgments are objective fall into one of two camps:

Such views are untenable concerning aesthetic judgments in general – art or environment

Hold some version of subjectivist, relativist and/or a noncognitivist view about aesthetic judgments

Reject these views about art, but have reservations about rejecting it when its about nature.

Ok – “

Guernica

is dynamic” Not Ok – “the Grand Tetons are majestic”

** This paperSlide3

Walton’s Position

The truth value of aesthetic judgments about a work of art depend on two things:

The perceptual properties a work actually has

The perceived status of such perceptual properties when a work is perceived in its correct category(ies) of art. Standard, contra standard, variableSlide4

Guernica. Pablo P

icasso. 1937.Slide5

Walton’s 4 Circumstances for Correct Perception (of Guernica

)

That it has a relatively large number of properties standard with respect to cubism.

That it is a better painting when perceived as a cubist paintingThat Picasso intended or expected it to be perceived as a cubist paintingThat the category of cubist paintings was well established in and recognized by the society in which Guernica was producedSlide6

Nature and Culture

Carlson believes the distinction between art and natural aesthetic judgments held by Walton and others based on the construction of the argument is inconsistent/implausible

Some judgments as nature seem to strike virtually everyone as true or false

Some other judgments seems like paradigms of aesthetic judgment in the way humans appreciate aesthetics.Cultural accounts of the aesthetic are the basic reason for a bifurcated view of aesthetic judgments .. But this is promising, and should not be simply rejected. Slide7

Nature and Walton’s Psychological Claim

The psychological claim: “The aesthetic judgments that seem true or false of a work are a function of the perceptual status of its perceptual properties given any category in which the work is perceived.”

Small elephant example

Exemplifies the standard, contra standard and variable categories initially applied to artwork onlySlide8

What about the psychological claim’s application to landscapes?

Example of the beach vs. tidal basin vs. seafloor

Example illustrates a shift of aesthetic response from “wild, glad emptiness” to “disturbing weirdness” with more information about the natural event you are experiencing aesthetically.

The standard, contra standard and variable classifications are useful here again in more accurately classifying a perception.Thus, the psychological implications of categorization that Walton only found possible in man-made art, also apply to natural environments. Slide9

Psychological 

Philosophical

This consistency in the psychological perceptions and categorizations between art and nature being proven, Carlson moves on to his more important questions about the correctness of such judgments.

Should he opt for the category-relative interpretation of aesthetic judgments of nature, or is it possible to consider certain categories of nature to be correct or incorrect (the same way art is handled)?Slide10

The Correct Categories of Nature

Thus the psychological claims proven to be possible above inform the truth value of aesthetic responses to nature.

So some categories of nature are true, and others are not.

There are easy cases of this – i.e. the small elephantThere are more difficult ones – whale = fish or mammal? (This is where perceptual properties may not be enough to decide a category.)Slide11

Preliminary Argument

Whale as fish or mammal example

We don’t produce but discover natural objects

So we don’t produce, but discover categories for natural objects.As art relies on art critics or historians for this type of knowledge, natural aesthetics will rely on naturalists or scientists. This at best shifts the burden of proof to those who defend category-relative interpretations. Slide12

Goal:

To prove that it is correct to perceive an object in the category of what it is, as opposed to what it appears to be, even in difficult cases where its perceptual properties do not themselves count toward one or the other categories being correct.

Example: a scenic coastline that appears to be natural, but is in fact man-madeSlide13

First Coastline Example - 65

Two indistinguishable coastlines – one natural one manmade.

On some level, we aesthetically appreciate them equally

At a “deeper” level, we don’t. And this is the more important level for aesthetic experience.Additionally, there are important distinctions between the two coastlines, and not appreciating these differences is negligent, if not dangerous. This provides grounds for calling something a “correct category,” even in cases that are unclear.And the conclusion depends neither on very broad or very different types of objects being compared. Slide14

Second Coastline Example - 66

There is an ethical argument for categorizing things correctly.

This is the best way to keep our aesthetics and ethics

inharmonyPlayboy centerfold example“If our aesthetic appreciation of nature helps to determine our ethical views concerning nature, then our aesthtic appreciation of nature should be as it in fact is, rather than as what it may appear to be. Implications for natural aesthetics may include safety or environmental concerns. What we know about that environment within its category will shape the ethical choices we make in our treatment of it.

This does not logically defend “discovering” correct categories, but it does establish ethical merit in using correct or

incorrect categories. Slide15

Conclusion

Carlson has kept aesthetic appreciation within the confines of a cultural account, the same way man-made art objects are treated. The difference is:

In art, art history and art criticism play a role as bodies of knowledge to inform aesthetic judgment.

For nature, natural history and natural science will fill this role. We can choose to simply appreciate nature formally, but the methods he has employed and the psychological/philosophical arguments he has made have provided a way to appreciate more appropriately and deeply.This is not only more interesting/fulfilling/appropriate for Carlson; it is essential.