/
ThisisanauthorgeneratedprepublisheddraftThenalversionisavailableonlin ThisisanauthorgeneratedprepublisheddraftThenalversionisavailableonlin

ThisisanauthorgeneratedprepublisheddraftThenalversionisavailableonlin - PDF document

joanne
joanne . @joanne
Follow
343 views
Uploaded On 2021-09-30

ThisisanauthorgeneratedprepublisheddraftThenalversionisavailableonlin - PPT Presentation

CambrigeJournalsOnlinedoi101017S0022226712000059crCambridgeUniversityPress2012ConjunctioncumulationandrespectivelyreadingsRuiPChavesLinguisticsDepartmentUniversityatBualoTheStateUniversityofNewYorkrc ID: 890954

kehler 2004 cxt dance 2004 kehler dance cxt sag 1998 sing head 2000 1989 eds 1987 forexample cation bbbb

Share:

Link:

Embed:

Download Presentation from below link

Download Pdf The PPT/PDF document "Thisisanauthorgeneratedprepublisheddraft..." is the property of its rightful owner. Permission is granted to download and print the materials on this web site for personal, non-commercial use only, and to display it on your personal computer provided you do not modify the materials and that you retain all copyright notices contained in the materials. By downloading content from our website, you accept the terms of this agreement.


Presentation Transcript

1 Thisisanauthor-generatedprepublisheddraf
Thisisanauthor-generatedprepublisheddraft.The nalversionisavailableonlineat CambrigeJournalsOnline (doi:10.1017/S0022226712000059).c\rCambridgeUniversityPress2012 Conjunction,cumulationandrespectivelyreadingsRuiP.ChavesLinguisticsDepartment{UniversityatBu aloTheStateUniversityofNewYorkrchaves@bu alo.eduAbstractSo-calledrespectivelyreadingshaveposedseriouschallengesfortheoriesofsyntaxandsemantics.SentenceslikeGeorgeandMartharespectivelydenouncedandweredenouncedbythegovernor(McCawley1998)showthatalthoughtheconjoinedverbalexpressionssharethesamesyntacticsubject,theydonotpredicatethatsubjectinthesameway;George(notMartha)denouncedthegovernor,andMartha(butnotGeorge)wasdenouncedbythegovernor.Postal(1998,160{163)andGawron&Kehler(2004,193{194)showthatthisphenomenonposesproblemsforcontemporarytheoriesofgrammarandarguethatitisparticularlyacutefortheorieswheresubcategorizationandpredicationarelinkedviauni cation.Astheseauthorsnote,theproblemisevenmoresevereinrespectivelyreadingsinvolving ller{gapconstructions.InthispaperIarguethattheseverityoftheseproblemshasbeenoverstatedandthatthedatadonotentailanyspecialdissociationbetweenpredication,subcategorization,orextraction.InthispaperIproposeanaccountwhichisfullycompatiblewithuni cation-basedtheoriesofgrammar.Gawron&Kehler(2004)proposeanaccountofrespectivelyphenomenawhichcoversaremarkablywiderangeofcases.ThatapproachreliesonaRespfoperator,whichisstipulatedtobeoptionallyovert.However,thisanalysisisarguablyproblematicbecausetherearesigni cantsemanticdi erencesbetweenre-spectivelyreadingswithandwithoutanovertrealizationof`respectively'.Rather,thedatasuggestthatrespectivelyreadingsmaybespecialcasesofmoregeneralphe-nomenawhichhappentocreateinterpretationscompatiblewiththesemanticsoftheadverb`respectively'.Thisexplainswhyrespectivelyreadingscanarisewithouttheadverb,anddoesnotrequirepositingadisconnectbetweenpredicationandsubcate-gorization.Infact,asentencewitharespectivelyreadingwillnotdi erinsyntacticorsemanticstructurefromsentenceswithoutsuchareading.1IntroductionEventhoughSueandKarenformsapluralNPthattriggerspluralsubject{ver

2 bagree-mentin(1),thissubjectphrasedoesno
bagree-mentin(1),thissubjectphrasedoesnotseemtobeinterpretedasapluralitybytheverbs IamgratefultotheanonymousrefereesoftheJournalofLinguisticsfortheircommentsandcriticism.Ialsothanktheaudiencesandrefereesoftheconferenceswherepreviousversionsofthisworkwerepresented,namelythe17thBiennialConferenceoftheLinguisticSocietyofNewZealand(UniversityofWaikato),andthe83rdAnnualMeetingoftheLinguisticSocietyofAmerica.ThanksisalsoduetoBrianGromforassistancesearchingGoogle'sN-Gramcorpus.1 in(1).Forexample,in(1a)KarenisnotanagentofjogandSueisnotanagentofdrive.Itisclear,however,thatsuchcoordinatesubjectNPsdoformasyntacticandsemanticsubjectbecauseofdatalike(2).Thus,respectivelyreadingsseemtocreateafundamentaldisconnectbetweensubcategorizationandpredication.(1)(a)SueandKarenjoganddriverespectively.(=`SuejogsandKarendrives.')(b)SueandKarenhiredBobandTimrespectively.(=`SuehiredBobandKarenhiredTim.')(2)(a)SueandKaren,wholoveeachotherverymuch,singanddancerespectively.(b)Theboyandthegirl(whoare)inthesamepictureareDutchandItalianrespec-tively.Postal(1998,136,160),Kehler(2002,125),andGawron&Kehler(2003,2004)pointoutthattheproblemismoresevereincasesof`long-distance'respectivelyreadings,suchas(3).Althoughbothpredicatessharethesamephraseextractedacross-the-board(ATB),theypredicateadi erentsubsetofitsdenotation.Postal(1998,163)arguesthattheproblemisasseverefortransformationalapproachesasitisfornon{transformationalapproaches,andlikeGawron&Kehler(2004,193)concludesthattheidentityconditionimposedbycoordinationmustbeweakenedsomehow.Thispaperwillattempttosolvethisproblem.(3)(a)[Whatbookandwhatmagazine]didJohnbuyandBillreadrespectively?(b)[Where]didMaryvacationandBilldecidetoliverespectively?(c)I nallymetSusan,Lynn,andMaryyesterday.Theyarethe[threesisters]thatBobhired,Johnpromoted,andBill redrespectively.Notethatthepresenceoftheadverbisnotnecessaryforrespectivelyreadingstoarise.Infact,iftheadverbisnotpresentthenotherreadingsareavailableaswell(collective,distributive,etc.).Forexample,SueandKarenhiredBobandTimcanmeanthatSuehiredBobandKarenhiredTim,orthatSueandKarencollectivelyhiredBobandTim,etc

3 ..InalltheaccountsthatIamfamiliarwith,th
..InalltheaccountsthatIamfamiliarwith,theoptionalityoftheadverbisleftwithoutanexplanationandassumedtobetheresultofarespectivelyoperator(Respf)whichcanbephoneticallynull.Iregardthisstipulationassuspect,andwillprovideanaccountthatexplainstheoptionalityoftheadverb.Kay(1989)arguesthatrespectivelyreadingsrequireaone-to-onemapping.Thus,in(1a)SueispairedwithjogandKarenwithdrive.Similarlyin(1b),SueisinsomesensepairedwithBob,andKarenispairedwithTim.Whensuchabijectivemappingisnotpossible,asin(4),boththerespectivelyreadingandtheadverbaredisallowed.(4)(a)SueandKarenjog(*respectively).(b)Suejogsandsings(*respectively).2 Moreover,McCawley(1998)notedthatthesebijectionscantargetanynumberofNPsinthesentence.Takeforexample(5a)below,whichismany{waysambiguous.Intheextreme,everyNPispair{wisemapped(i.e.`SuesentabooktoBobandKarensentamagazinetoTim'),butitcouldalsobethecasethatonlytwoNPsarepair{wisemapped(e.g.`SuesentabooktoBobandTim,andKarensentamagazinetoBobandTim',amongothers).Similarly,(5b)illustratesacasewhereonlythecomplementNPsareinvolvedinthebijection,notthesubject.Thepointisthatrespectivelyreadingscantargetanynumberofco{arguments.(5)(a)SueandKarensentabookandamagazinetoBobandTimrespectively.(b)IgaveTomandMaryabookandamagazinerespectively.Amajortenetofmosttheoriesofgrammaristhattheprocessofsemanticcomposi-tionshouldbeassimpleaspossible.Insometheories,semanticcompositionisviewedasideallybeingmonotonic.1Shieber(1988)statesthatagrammarissemanticallymonotonicif,foreveryphraseadmittedbythegrammar,thesemanticstructureofeachimmediatesubphrasesubsumessomeportionofthesemanticstructureoftheentirephrase.Inotherwords,forsemanticcompositiontooperatemonotonicallyitmustnotallowrepresentationspreviouslybuilttobesubsequentlychangedordeleted.Amono-tonicsemantictheoryismaximallyparsimoniousbecauseitsimplyjoinsmeaningswithoutresortingtonon{trivialcomputationsthatleadtolossofinformationaboutpreviouslyas-sembledrepresentations.Whetherornotallofnaturallanguagesemanticscanbehandledbymonotoniccompositionisdebatable,butoneofthephenomenathathastraditionallybeenevokedtonecessitatenon{monotonicoperati

4 onsispreciselyrespectivelyreadings.2Take
onsispreciselyrespectivelyreadings.2TakeforexampleSueandKarenjoganddrive.Allexistingaccountsof`respectively'arebasedontheassumptionthatSueandKarenyieldsaplurality{e.g.ani-sumlikesk,orsomeequivalentpluralmeaning{butthatatasubsequentstageofsemanticcom-position,skisdestroyedinordertoproducejog(s)^drive(k).ThepluralitythatwasassembledbyparsingthesubjectNPSueandKarenisnotpresentinthe nalsemanticrepresentation.InthispaperIshowthatrespectivelyreadingscanbemodeledmonoton-ically,maintainingatightcorrespondencebetweensyntaxandsemantics.Inparticular,thesyntacticandsemanticrepresentationofsentenceslikeSueandKarenhiredBobandTimwillbethesameirrespectiveofarespectivelyinterpretation.ThesameappliestoSueandKarensinganddance.Inmyaccountthesesentencesallowareadingwhichiscompatiblewiththesemanticsoftheadverb`respectively'.Thepaperisstructuredasfollows.Section2reviewspreviousaccountsofrespectivelyphenomenaanddiscussestheirshortcomings.Newdataisprovidedtosuggestthatrespec-tivelyreadingsareofadi erentnaturethanusuallyassumed.InSection3itisarguedthatthesentencemeaningswhicharecompatiblewiththepresenceoftheadverb`respectively'arespecialcasesoftwoindependentphenomena.Asaresultofthisreconceptualization, 1Thishasbeenadvocatedbyavarietyofauthors,foravarietyoftheoriesofgrammar,suchasAlshawi&Crouch(1992),Shieber&Schabes(1992),Pollard&Sag(1994,323),Steedman(1996,7,91),Steedman(2001,1,5{7,23,87),Halvorsen(1988),Dalrymple(1999),andAsher&Lascarides(2003,118),interalia.2SeePullum&Gazdar(1982,484)andGazdaretal.(1985,150).3 sentenceswithrespectivelyreadingsdonothavespecialsyntacticorsemanticrepresenta-tionsanddonotresorttonon{monotonicandoptionallycovertoperators.Myproposalcaninprinciplebeadoptedbyanytheoryofgrammar,andinSection4Ishow,byformal-izingmyaccountinHead-DrivenPhraseStructureGrammar(Pollard&Sag,1994),thatPostal(1998,160{163)andGawron&Kehler(2004,194)areincorrectinclaimingthatuni cation-basedframeworksareparticularlyill-suitedtohandlerespectivelyreadings.2Previousaccounts2.1SyntacticaccountsGoodall(1987),Moltmann(1992)andothersproposethat`respectively'triggersasyn-tacticoperationint

5 hepresenceofcoordinationthattransformsas
hepresenceofcoordinationthattransformsasentencewithphrasalconjunctionsintoclausalconjunctions.However,McCawley(1968,297),Chomsky(1972,123,note26),Stockwell,Schachter&Partee(1973),Pullum&Gazdar(1982),Kay(1989),Dalrymple&Kehler(1995),andMcCawley(1998)noteddatalike(6),whichrefutethisassumption.(6)(a)Those vemenarePolish,Irish,Armenian,Italian,andChinese(respectively).(b)TheyliveinChicagoandNewYork(respectively).(c)Thesuccessivedescendantsofmyfruit\rywillbeheavier,respectively,thanthesuccessivedescendantsofyours.Kay(1989)showsthat`respectively'canonlyestablishaone-to-onemappingbetweendenotataifthereisanindependentranking.Thus,thesentencein(7a)isacceptablebuttheonein(7b)isnot.3(7)(a)Thethreebeststudentsreceivedthethreebestscoresrespectively.(b)#Thestudentswerepleasedbytheirscores,respectively.In(8)Iprovidemoreexampleslackingconjunctionaltogether.AsKay(1989,2004)observes,thecorrectgeneralizationisthataone-to-onemappingbetweenpluralitiesisestablishedviasomepragmaticrankingduetocontext,surfaceorder,orworldknowledge.(8)(a)Thefollowingtwosectionswilldealwiththesetwoissuesrespectively.(b)Twodi erentformulasweretested,respectively,bytwogroupsofpatientswithvariousperiodontaldisorders.(c)Thiscontroversyrevolvedaroundtheplacewhereanewmeetinghouseshouldbeset,andasthepartiescouldnotagree,theybuilttwoinplacestheyrespectivelychose. 3AsKaynotes,thiscontrastswithexpressionslikerespective,whichonlyoccurifthemappingisnotachievedviaanindependentlyestablishedranking(e.g.thestudentswerepleasedbytheirrespectivescoresvs.#thethreebeststudentsreceivedthethreerespectivehighestscores).Formoreonrespective,di erent,andthesameseeCarlson(1987),Kay(1989,2004),Keenan(1992)andBarker(2007)amongothers.4 Insum,thedataindicatethattheso{called`respectivelyconstruction'cannotbeseenasasyntacticoperationoncoordinatestructures.Inthesedata,abijectionisestablishedbetweenplural{denotingnominalphrases,whichstronglysuggeststhatthecorrectaccountissemanticinnature.2.2SemanticaccountsLink(1991)proposesaspecialconjunctionmeaningthatformsorderedtuplesusinghigher{dimensional{abstractionslikexyandallowspredicatest

6 odistributeoverthem.Forexample,theconjun
odistributeoverthem.Forexample,theconjunctionGeorgeandNickyieldsatuple(g;n)whichisthenusedtoproduceapropositionalconjunctionasshownin(9).Suchanaccountisnotmonotonicbecausethei-sumscorrespondingtotheNPsGeorgeandNickandMarthaandHoneyaredestroyedwhencombinedwiththeverbalsemantics.4(9)(a)GeorgeandNickhateMarthaandHoney,respectively.x1x2:[y1y2[hate(x1;y1)^hate(x2;y2)](m;h)](g;n),hate(g;m)^hate(n;h)(b)GeorgeandMarthaaredrinkinganddancing,respectively.xy[drink(x)^dance(y)](g;m),drink(g)^dance(m)Gawron&Kehler(2004)proposeamorecomprehensiveaccount,whichscalesuptonon{coordinatecases.Conjunctionissystematicallyviewedassumformation:nominalconjunctionyieldsindividualsumswhileverbalconjunctionyieldspropertysums.ApragmaticallyestablishedsequencingfunctionfcanaccessthesurfaceofconjunctsandaRespfoperatorproducestherespectivelyreadings.TheRespfoperatorissimilartoadistributionoperatorDistrinthesensethatitattachestoapluralicentityandoperatesoveritsmembers.As(10)illustrates,Respftakestwoarguments:averbalrepresentationandanominalrepresentation.(10)SueandKarenjoganddrive.Respf(jogtdrive)(s_k)=jog(s)tdrive(k)TheanalysisofSueandKarenloveBobandTimproceedsasfollows.ThesubjectandobjectNPscorrespondtothejoinss_kand_k.ThedistributionDistrcopiestheverbmeaningovereachconjunctDistr(love(tt))=love()tlove(t),andthentheoperatorRespfcombinesthisVPwiththesubject:Respf(loves()tloves(t))(s_k)=loves()(s)tloves(t)(k).BasicallythesameappliestorespectivelyreadingswithoutNPconjunction.LikeLink's,thisaccountisnon{monotonic.Atsomepointintheprocessofsemanticcompositionwehaveani-sumfortherepresentationofaconjoinedNP,butlaterthatrepresentationdisappears.ThereisnorepresentationfortheNPpluralityinthe nalsemanticsofthesentence.Thispointisimportantbecauseitreverberatesinthesyntax{semanticsinterface.IfGawron&Kehler(2004,193)areright,notheoryofgrammarmayassumethatverbsdirectlypredicatetheNPvalentsthattheysubcategorize.Thereisawaysthepotentialforarespectivelyreading,inwhichcaseRespfintervenesandcausesaverbtopredicateonlyastrictsubsetofitsargument'sdenotation.Mymaingoalisto 4Arelatedaccountthatfocusesontheverb

7 instead,vialexicalrules,isFast(2005).5 s
instead,vialexicalrules,isFast(2005).5 showthatthereisanalternativeanalysisofrespectivelyreadingswhichdoesnotcreatesuchadividebetweensyntaxandsemantics.Semanticcompositioncanremainsimpleandmonotonic,andsubcategorizationcanoperateintandemwithpredication,asassumedbycontemporarysyntactictheories.ThereseemtobethreeempiricalproblemswiththeaccountinGawron&Kehler(2004).First,althougheveryoccurrenceoftheadverb`respectively'isassumedtotriggertheinsertionofaRespfoperator,itispossibleforaRespfoperatortobeinsertedwithouttheovertpresenceoftheadverb.Theproblemisthatnothingbutastipulationcapturesthefactthattheadverbcanbeoptionalinrespectivelyinterpretations.Ideally,theoptionalityoftheadverbshouldfollowfromindependentlymotivatedfactors.Asecondproblemisthatthefmechanismthatcapturesthecontextually{determinedorderingsisclaimedtoonlyapplytonon{atomicreferents.AccordingtoGawron&Kehler(2004,174),thiscorrectlycapturestheoddnessofcaseslike#A/The/Everymansmiledrespectively,whereatleastoneoftheNPsissingularandthereforehasnopropersubpartsinwhichtomapanything.However,thisstancemaybeexcessive.ThenativespeakersofEnglishthatIhaveconsultedaccepttheexamplein(11)below,foundintheWeb1T5{gramVersion1ofGoogle'sN{GramCorpus,whichisalsothesourceoftheotherattestedexamplesincludedinthispaper,referencedbytheirURLs.Inthisdatapointthepresenceof`respectively'isallowedbecausearankingofpartiesandtheircostsiseasytoconceptualize,eventhougheachpartyisasingularNP.Theadverb`respectively'isfelicitousbecausetheuniversallyquanti edsubjectcanoutscopetheverbandobtainaninterpretationwherethereisadi erent`bearing'eventforeachparty/cost.(11)Whiletherelationshipofthepartiesremainsamicable,itisessentialthatanagree-mentbereachedastothecosts[that]eachpartywillrespectivelybear.(www.innovasafe.com/doc/blatt.doc)ThethirdproblemisthatGawron&Kehler(2004)predictthatthereshouldbenodi erencebetweenrespectivelyreadingswithorwithouttheadverb,becauseinbothcasestherelevantinterpretationsareproducedbyRespf.BelowIprovideempiricalevidenceagainstthisprediction.Considerthesentencein(12).Thereisapragmaticallyodd rstinterpretationwherethe

8 sametwentyexecutiveswerepromotedanddemot
sametwentyexecutiveswerepromotedanddemotedonthesameday.Thisisthe`strictidentity'reading,whereeachconjunctpredicatesexactlythesamedependent.However,thereisalsoa`weakidentity'reading,whereoutoftwentyexecutivessomewerepromotedandothersweredemoted.Thelatterseemstobewhatisusuallycalledarespectivelyreading,butinfactthisisnottrue.Theexamplein(12)actuallyworsenswiththeovertpresenceoftheadverb`respectively'.(12)Today,twentyexecutiveswerepromotedanddemoted(#respectively).Thissuggeststhatthereadingin(12)isrelatedto{butnotthesameas{are-spectivelyreading.Inthiscasetheadverb`respectively'isnotfelicitousbecausethereisnoindependentrankingofexecutives.SuchdataareunexpectedinGawron&Kehler(2004).In(13)Iprovidemoreexamplesofsentenceswithinterpretationsthatappeartoberespectivelyreadingsbutwhichcannotco{occurfelicitouslywiththeadverb.6 (13)(a)Thefrontandthebackoftheshiparecalledthebowandthestern,butwhichiswhich?(b)Weknowhousesfourand vearetheSwedeandtheGerman,butwhichiswhich?(www.everything2.com/index.pl?node id=984348)(c)GoodmanandIarelikeDrysdaleandKoufax.Yeah,butwhichoneiswhich?(sfgate.com/cgi-bin/blogs/mlasalle/detail?blogid=38&entry id=10946)(d)CaesarandIareas reandwater,butastowhichiswhichyoumustjudgeforyourself.(TalbotMundy,inTrosofSamothrace,Appleton-Century,1934,Chp.XXXI,p.168)Thedatain(13)alsoindicatethatthesurfacepairingbetweennominalconjunctsisnotagrammaticalconstraint,sinceitcanbecanceledbycertaincontinuations.Inotherwords,respectivelyreadingswithoutanovertadverbarebiasedtowardspresentationorder,whereasrespectivelyreadingswithanovertadverbarerestrictedtoit.5Anotherargumentagainstthenotionthatrespectivelyreadingswithorwithoutad-verbsarisefromthesameRespfoperatorisbasedonthecontrastin(14).Sincebothsentencesareonlyfelicitousifinterpretedwitharespectivelyreading,bothshouldrequirethepresenceofacovertoperatorRespf.Butwhereasexample(14a)toleratestheovertrealizationoftheadverb,(14b)becomeslessacceptablewiththeovertrealizationoftheadverb.Thefunctionoftheadverb`respectively'istosingleoutacertainkindofinterpre-tationinalargersetofpossibleinterpretations.Incaseslike(14b){where

9 noambiguityisusuallyperceivedbecausehusb
noambiguityisusuallyperceivedbecausehusbandandwifeissuchastrongbinomialexpression{thepresenceoftheadverbisunwarranted.ForGawron&Kehler(2004)itshouldnotmatterifRespfisovertorcovert,andyetthedataindicatethatitdoes.(14)(a)TomandMaryaretallandshort.(TomandMaryaretallandshortrespectively.)(b)TomandMaryarehusbandandwife.(?#TomandMaryarehusbandandwiferespectively.)Thefactthattheadverb`respectively'canaccesssurfaceorderisnotremarkable.Manyotherexpressionslike`theformer',`thelatter',`inthatorder',`conversely',`con-trariwise,and`viceversa',seemtoaccesssurfaceordermetalinguistically,evenintheabsenceofconjunction,asthedatain(15)illustrate.IconcludethatsuchexpressionsarecontextualinthesenseofKay(1989),andhavethemeanstoaccesssurfaceorder.Idonotdiscusshowsuchaccessworksasthisisanindependentquestionbeyond`respectively'.(15)(a)[CraigJones]iisadi erentkindof lm{makerfrom[StuartLee]j.While[theformer]iismorecomfortablewithabstractconcepts,[thelatter]jlikestoconveyhisthoughtsasdirectlyaspossible. 5Iconjecturethatthesurfaceorderbiasisduetocognitivelimitationsalsoseenincross{serialdepen-dencies(Bachetal.(1986)showedthatserialdependencies`ABCABC'areeasiertoprocessthan`ABCCBA')andinmultipleextraction(seeFodor(1978)forprocessingdicultywhenextractionpathsarecrossed).7 (b)About20%of[men]'sunderwearisboughtby[women],andviceversa.(=`About20%ofwomen'sunderwearisboughtbymen.')(c)[Worms]mayhaveevolvedfrom[arthropods]ratherthantheotherwayaround.(d)[TheHobbit]waswrittenbefore[TheLordoftheRings],butIdidn'treadtheminthatorder.Ihavetriedtoarguethatso{calledrespectivelyreadingsarenothingbutasubsetofamoregeneralkindofreading.Thelatterareoftennotcompatiblewiththepresenceoftheadverb,asshownin(12)and(13).ThismeansthatRespfismissingimportantgeneralizations:ontheonehand,itistoorestrictivetomodelthe`respectivelyreadings'thatarisewithout`respectively'likein(12),whileontheother,itdoesnotcorrespondtotheactualsemanticcontributionmadebytheadverb.IthusrejecttheexistenceofanoptionallycovertoperatorlikeRespf,andseekanalternativeanalysis.3Analternativeaccountof`respectively'readingsInthissectionIexplorethepos

10 sibilityofrespectivelyreadingsbeingepiph
sibilityofrespectivelyreadingsbeingepiphenomenal.Theclaimisthattwodi erentkindsofphenomenayieldinterpretationsthat{incertainconditions{happentobecompatiblewiththesemanticsofthe`respectively'adverb.Togivearoughanalogy,considerpluralsubject{verbagreement.Therearethreecom-pletelydi erentphenomenainEnglishthatcantriggerit.Oneisnounpluralization(themorphologicalprocessbywhichasingularnouncanbeusedtoobtainapluralnoun),thesecondisnon-Booleanconjunction(whichyieldsapluralitywhenconjoiningsingularnominalexpressions),andthethirdiscollectivenouncoercion(e.g.Thefacultyarevotingthemselvesaraise).Althoughpluralization,conjunction,andcollective-to-pluralcoercionareclearlynotthesamephenomenon,theycanallyieldnominalexpressionsthatcanoccurassubjectsandtriggerpluralsubject{verbagreement.Myhypothesisisthattwounrelatedandindependentphenomenacanyieldinterpretationswhichincludewhatareusuallyviewedasrespectivelyreadings(i.e.casesinwhichtherearebijectionsbetweendenotata).Incertaincircumstances,theadverb`respectively'canbeaddedfordisam-biguationpurposes.Thispredictstheoptionalityoftheadverbandthesubtledi erencesbetweenrespectivelyreadingswithorwithouttheadverb.Section3.1focusesoncasesthatdonotinvolveverbalconjunctionandarguesthattheseareakindofcumulativereadinginthesenseofScha(1981).Section3.2dealswithcasesthatinvolveverbalconjunction,andarguesthatthesefollowfromhowthesyntax{semanticsinterfaceofconjunctionintegratesshareddependents.InSection3.3theroleoftheadverbisdiscussed.3.1Cumulativequanti cationreadingsThesentencesin(16)haveacumulativequantificationinterpretaton(Scha,1981,497).6Forinstance,inacumulativereadingof(16a)therearemanypossiblemappings 6Othertermshadbeenusedintheliterature.E.g.,Kroch(1974)usestheterm`seriallydistributive'.8 betweenthesoldiersandthetargetstheyhit.AsBeck&Sauerland(2000)andothersnote,datalike(16)indicatethatsuchreadingsalsooccurwithconjunction.(16)(a)Twosoldiershittwotargets.(b)Severalcriticspraisedsomemovies.(c)700Dutchcompaniesused10000Americancomputers.(d)Thesedotscorrespondtothosecities.(e)JimandFrankwanttomarrytwodentists.Variousaccountshavebeenpropo

11 sedforsuchreadings.7Forexample,Kroch(197
sedforsuchreadings.7Forexample,Kroch(1974,205)andScha(1981,497)usemeaningpostulateslike(17).(17)P( ; )=(8 02 !9 02 ^P( 0; 0))^(8 02 !9 02 ^P( 0; 0))Krifka(1989),Sternefeld(1998)andmanyothersmakeuseofa**-operatortoasimilare ect.Formypurposes,itisnotimportantwhichanalysisisadopted,andIremainagnosticwithrespecttothischoice.Figure1showsthereadingsthat(17)allowsforacumulativeinterpretationof(16a).Crucially,twoofthesearebijections.Infact,whendiscussingasentencelike(16a),Link(1991)writesthat`thesituationdescribed(...)isaspecialcumulativereadingwhere,inaddition,therelationisabijectivefunction'.t1t2s1s2t1t2s1s2t1t2s1s2t1t2s1s2t1t2s1s2 bbbb bbbb bbbb bbbb bbbb bbbb bbbb bbbb bbbb bbbb bbbb bbbb bbbb Figure1:Respectivelyreadingsasaninstanceofcumulativereadings.Ithereforeproposethatsomerespectivelyreadingsaresimplyabijectivecumulativein-terpretation.Thefunctionsoftheadverb`respectively'istosingleoutoneofthebijectiverelationsinthesetofpossibleindependentlyobtainedcumulativeinterpretations.Thisexplainswhythepresenceoftheadverbisoptional,andwhyrespectivelyreadingsdonotarisewhentheNPsaredisjoinedratherthanconjoined.8Tobeclear,inthisviewrespectivelyinterpretationsareaconsequenceofcumulativereadings,andthefunctionoftheadverbistopickacumulativereadingthatisbijectiveandsatis esapragmatic-orlinearization-basedranking.Thisapproachmakesseveralpredictions.Cumulativequanti cationcanapplytopredicateswithmorethantwoarguments,andwhenitdoes,itdoesnotforceallargumentstobecumulativelyinterpreted.Forexample,anytwoNPsin(18)canbeinterpretedcumulatively(orallthree). 7SeeforexampleBartsch(1973);Kroch(1974);Scha(1981);Krifka(1989);Roberts(1987);Schein(1993);Schwarzschild(1996);Sternefeld(1998);Landman(2000).8SeeGawron&Kehler(2004,202{204)formoreaboutdisjunctionand`respectively'.9 (18)Twostudentssentfourletterstothreecongressmen.Onestudentmayhavemailedtwoletterstothethreecongressmen,whiletheotherstu-dentmailedthetwootherletters;orthetwostudentscollectivelysentonelettertoonecongressmanandanotherlettertotheremainingcongressmen.Thetotalofcombinationsis24(=243),minusotherreadingsduetoscopeambigu

12 ity(e.g.Link1998:54).Thishasconsequences
ity(e.g.Link1998:54).Thishasconsequencesforthecurrentaccountofrespectivelyreadings.ItentailsthatsentenceswiththreepluralNPsareambiguousinessentiallythesameway.Thispredictionisborneoutindatalike(19),fromMcCawley(1998)andGawron&Kehler(2004),where`respectively'allowsalloranytwoNPstobemappedbijectively.Thisfollowswithoutstipulationifsuchreadingsarejustspecialcasesofcumulativereadings,asproposedabove.(19)GeorgeandMarthasentabombandanastylettertothepresidentandthegovernorrespectively.CumulativitycanalsotargetNPsthatarenotco-argumentsofthesameverb,asshownbyexamplesinvolvingadjunctslike(20).Inthesecasesthecumulationprocessseemstotargetthepredicatesinandcausing,whichcanbearguedtotakeasargumentsaneventualityandanominal.ItisthereforetemptingtoassumethateventsarestructuredmereologicallyasinBach(1986),andthatin(e;x)andcause(e;y)canbeinterpretedcumulatively.FormorediscussionseeforexampleSchein(1993,ch.9).(20)Fivealarmsmalfunctionedintwolocations,causingfouraccidents.Whatevertheproperaccountofcumulativereadingsis,myclaimisthatitwillpredictthebijectivemappingsthat`respectively'requires,amongmanyotherreadings.Iusetheadmittedlyoversimpli edaccountin(17)forexpositionpurposesonly,butmoresophis-ticatedapproachescanbeadopted,likethegeneralizedPPartoperatorofSchwarzschild(1990,1996).Crucially,however,noneoftheaboveaccountscandealwithrespectivelyreadingsthatinvolvepredicateconjunction,likethatin(21a).(21)a.Fortheirtalentexposition,thetopthreepageantwinnerssang,breathed re,andplayedthekazoo(respectively).b.Fortheirtalentexposition,[thetopthreepageantwinners]isang,theyibreathed re,andtheyiplayedthekazoo(#respectively).AsGawron&Kehler(2004,200)show,eventhePPartoperatoraccountinSchwarzschild(1996,88)cannotexplainwhy(21a)hasarespectivelyreadingbut(21b)doesnot.Gawron&Kehler(2004,199)alsoobservethatthePPartoperatorislimitedtorelationsamongindividual-levelgroups,anddoesnotextendtocasesthatinvolverelationsthatincludeproperty-levelgroups.Gawron&Kehlertakesuchdatatoshowthatpredicatescannotdirectlypredicatetheirdependents,butIargueotherwisebelow.10 3.2DependentsharinginconjunctionAsalreadydi

13 scussedinSection2.2,sentenceslike(12)abo
scussedinSection2.2,sentenceslike(12)above,repeatedherein(22),canbesaidtohavetwokindsofreadings.(22)Today,twentyexecutiveswerepromotedanddemoted.Inthe`strictidentity'reading,twentyexecutiveswerebothpromotedanddemoted(per-hapsbecauseofacomputerglitch).Thisreadingissomewhatimplausiblebecauseofworldknowledge,butwouldotherwisebethepreferredinterpretation(comparewithTwentyex-ecutiveswereinterviewedandsurveyed).Thereadingisonewheretheexecutivesthatwerepromotedaredi erentfromtheexecutiveswhogotdemoted(a`weakidentity'read-ing).Thelatterinterpretationissimilar{butnotidenticalto{arespectivelyreading:thepresenceoftheadverbisnotallowedbecausethedenotataofthesubjectlackanindependentranking.Arguably,thesentencein(23)alsohasstrict/weakidentityreadings.Theweakreadingiswhatisusuallycalledarespectivelyreading,sinceitcanbeforcedbyaddingtheadverb`respectively'.Intheabsenceoftheadverb,thestrictreadingisthepreferredone.(23)TomandFredsanganddanced.Technicaldi erencesaside,mostaccountsofVPcoordinationassumethatconjunctsmustnecessarilysharethesubject(i.e.musthavea`strictidentity'reading),asshowninFigure2.Thisexplainstheobservedsubject{verbagreementandsemanticinterpretation.S9x(man(x)^sing(x)^dance(x)) NPP:9x(man(x)^P(x)) amanVPx3:sing(x3)^dance(x3) VPx1:sing(x1) singsVPQ:x3:Q(x3)^dance(x3) ConjP:Q:x3:Q(x3)^P(x3) andVPx2:dance(x2) dancesFigure2:ShareddependentidentityHowever,inlightofambiguousexampleslike(22)above,Iwillrevisetheanalysisofconjunctionsothatanydependentsthataresharedbyconjunctsareeitherequated(`strictidentity')orcumulated(`weakidentity').Theformeryieldsthesameresultas11 inFigure2andthelatteryieldsakindofinterpretationofwhichrespectivelyreadingsareasubset.Fortunately,thereisasimpleoperationthatcansuccinctlycapturealltherelevantpatterns:Link's`'sumoperator.Inordertomodelnon-Booleannominalconjunction,Link(1983)resortstoasumrelation`'interpretedasajoinoperatorinamereologicaldomain:[[xy]]=[[x]]t[[y]].Thisde nitiondoesnotruleoutthepossibilitythatx=y,inwhichcasethesumdoesnotyieldaplurality.Thisfollowsfromthefactthatthejoin`t'isidempotent(i.e.8x[xtx=x]).9Formally,

14 Link'ssumencapsulatesexactlywhatisnecess
Link'ssumencapsulatesexactlywhatisnecessarytodealwiththetworeadingsof(22a),andconsequently,therespectivelyreadingsin(22b).Theproposedgeneralizationisstatedin(24)asaconditiononthesyntax{semanticsinterfaceofconjunction.InSection3.5Iarguethat(24)shouldbegeneralizedtootherkindsofdependencies.(24)SharedDependentConditionforConjunction(informal)Predicationdependenciessharedbyconjunctsarecombinedvia`'.Iwillformalize(24)byaugmentingthesemanticcontentoftheconjunctionand.Forsimpli cation,IassumethatthesemanticsofconjunctiononlytakestwoconjunctsQandP.10Ithusproposethelexicalentryin(25).Here,P[x0;:::;xn]andQ[y0;:::;yn]aretwoconjunctswithexactlyn(n0)freevariables,eachcorrespondingtoashareddependent.Thevariablescorrespondingtotheshareddependentsarecombinedvia`'.(25)Conjunction(preliminary)and:P:Q:z0:::zn:Q[x0:::xn]^P[y0:::yn]^z0=(x0y0)^:::^zn=(xnyn)InVPcoordinationthereisexactlyoneshareddependent:thesubject.ThismeansthatthevariablesofthesubjectsselectedbyeachoftheVPconjunctsarecombinedvia`'.Asaconsequence,thesevariablesareeitherequatedorcumulated.Ifequated,bothVPspredicatethesameentity(`strictidentity').Ifcumulated,eachVPpredicatesadi erentpartoftheplurality(`weakidentity').ThisisshowninFigure3. 9PrincipleCofBindingtheorypredictsthatconjunctscannotbeco-referential,asin*TomiandTomileft,*BatmanandBruceWaynehasdiedtoday,and*myfatherandmydadarrived.Mattersaremorecomplexthanthis,however,sinceco-referentialconjunctscanoccurincertaincases:tellmeaboutJohnasafatherandJohnasahusband.SeevanEijck(1983,99)onexampleslikehisagedservantandthesubsequenteditorofhiscollectedpaperswaswithhimathisdeathbed,andHoeksema(1988)ondataliketheMorningStarandtheEveningStararethesameplanet,agreatmanandagoodfatherhaspassedaway,and*myheroandHoudinihaspassedaway.10SeeSection4.2foranaccountthatcandealwithanynumberofconjunctsanddependents.12 VPz:sing(e1;x1)^dance(e2;x2)^z=(x1x2) VPx:sing(x) singVPQ:z:Q(x1)^dance(x2)^z=(x1x2) ConjP:Q:z:Q(x1)^P(x2)^z=(x1x2) andVPx:dance(x) danceFigure3:Non-deterministicdependentsharingIftheobtainedcoordinateVPcombineswithasubjectlikeTomandSue,weobtainthe

15 representationin(26).Thearrow`7! 'indica
representationin(26).Thearrow`7! 'indicatesbeta-reduction.(26)TomandSuesinganddance.(z:sing(x1)^dance(x2)^z=(x1x2))(ts)7! sing(x1)^dance(x2)^(ts)=(x1x2)Ifx1=x2then`'doesnotformapluralityandweobtainareadingwhereTomandSuearebothagentsofsinginganddancing(i.e.z=x1=x2).Conversely,ifx1=x2then`'isinterpretedasaplurality-formingcumulationandweobtainareadingwheretts=x1tx2.Because`'isasymmetricrelation,inthelattercaseitisnotknownwhethert=x1ands=x2orift=x2ands=x1.Thisindeterminacycanberesolvedbyaddingtheadverb`respectively'.Thatistheadverb'sfunction.TheaccountscalestootherkindsofpluralNPsubjects,like(27).Asbefore,if`'isinterpretedasequalitythenallstudentssanganddanced,andif`'isinterpretedasaplurality-formingcumulationthensomestudentssangwhileotherstudentsdanced.(27)Severalstudentssinganddance.(P:9x(student(x)^P(x)))(z:dance(x1)^sing(x2)^z=(x1x2))7! 9x(student(x)^sing(x1)^dance(x2)^x=(x1x2))AsdiscussedinSection2.2,thisfallsshortofbeingatruerespectivelyreadingbe-cause(27)doesnotallowthepresenceoftheadverb`respectively'.Theremustbeanindependentrankingbetweendenotatainordertoobtainatruerespectivelyreading.Outoftheblue,(27)exhibitsnosuchranking,andtherefore`respectively'isnotallowed.Conversely,incaseslikeRobinandKimarecousins.TheyliveinChicagoandNewYork(respectively),anindependentrankingisprovided,andthereforetheadverbcanbeused.Thebijectionforcedbythepresenceoftheadverb`respectively'insentenceslikeTomandFredsanganddancedholdsbetweentheatomsinthedenotationoftheplural13 NPandtheeventualitiesdenotedbytheconjoinedVP.IthusassumethatverbscomewithNeo-Davidsonianeventualityarguments,asarguedbyKamp(1979),Partee(1984),Higginbotham(1985),Bach(1986),Carlson(1987),Krifka(1989),Parsons(1990),andPustejovsky(1991),interalia.Supportforthiscomesfromwell-knownevidencethateventscanbeboundanaphorically,modi edbyanon-restrictiverelativeclause,dis-tributed,compared,andintensi ed:(28)(a)FredstabbedJones.Ithappenedatmidnight.(b)Kimevadedthepolice,whichisnotaneasythingtodo.(c)JohncalledeveryMonday.(=`ForallpastMondaysJohncalled.')(d)Iloveyoumorethanyouloveme.(e)Fredissogoingtojail.

16 Ifsucheventualitiesexist,thentheirconjun
Ifsucheventualitiesexist,thentheirconjunctionshouldalsoformapluraleventuality.Thisisempiricallysupportedbytheadverbialsin(29),whichpredicatetheconjoinedpluraleventuality.IthusfollowCarlson(1987,540{542),Lasersohn(1995,Chapter14),Gawron&Kehler(2004)andmanyothersinassumingthatplurality-formingconjunc-tioncanoperatecross-categorially:nominalconjunctionyieldsanominalpluralityandpredicateconjunctionyieldsapluraleventuality.(29)(a)Often,[[Igotothebeach]e1and[yougotothecity]e2]e1e2.(b)She[[gotdressed]e1and[driedherhair]e2]e1e2,[intenminutes].(c)Youcan'tsimultaneously[[drink]e1and[drive]e2]e1e2.(d)Whydidhe[[closethedoor]e1and[openthewindow]e2]e1e2?Accordingly,theconjunctionin(25)abovemustberevisedsothatitformsapluralitywiththedenotataoftheconjuncts.DrawingfromLink(1983)andKrifka(1990),Iadopttheconjunctionin(30),wherethe 1and 2variablescorrespondtoindividualsoreventu-alitiesdenotedbytheconjuncts.Iftheconjunctsareverbal,soistheplurality,andiftheconjunctsarenominal,soistheplurality.Nothinghingesonthisparticularformalization,however,asotherapproachestoconjunctionlikeLasersohn(1995),Schwarzschild(1996),andLandman(2000)canbeadoptedinstead.(30)Conjunction(revised)and:P:Q:z0:::zn:9 ( =( 1 2)^Q( 1)[x0:::xn]^P( 2)[y0;:::yn]^z0=(x0y0)^:::^zn=(xnyn))Therevisedconjunctionin(30)allowsVPconjunctiontobemodeledasshownin(31).The variablesarerenamedaseforperspicuity.In(31a)wecombineandwithdanced.In(31b)wecombinesangwithanddanced.Notethatasumisformedwiththedenotationoftheconjuncts,andthesharedsubjectdependentiscombinedvia`'.Finally,in(31c)wecombineTomandFredwithsanganddanced.14 (31)[[TomandFred]NP[sanganddanced]VP]Sa.(P:Q:z:9e(e=(e1e2)^Q(x1)(e1)^P(x2)(e2)^z=(x1x2)))(x:e:dance(e;x))7! Q:z:(e3=(e1e2)^Q(x1)(e1)^dance(e2;x2)^z=(x1x2)b.(Q:z:9e(e=(e1e2)^Q(x1)(e1)^dance(e2;x2)^9z(z=(x1x2)))(x:e:sing(e;x))7! z:(e=(e1e2)^sing(e1;x1)^dance(e2;x2)^z=(x1x2))c.(z:9e(e=(e1e2)^sing(e1;x1)^dance(e2;x2)^z=(x1x2)))(tf)7! 9e(e=(e1e2)^sing(e1;x1)^dance(e2;x2)^(tf)=(x1x2))Exactlyasbefore,thesemanticrepresentationobtainedin(31)allowstwodistinctinterpretations.If`'is

17 interpretedasequalitythenwehavethereadin
interpretedasequalitythenwehavethereadingwhereeachconjunctpredicatesthesameplurality(i.e.(ts)=(x1=x2)),andif`'isinterpretedasaplurality-formingcumulationthenwehaveareadingwhereeachverbpredicatesadi erentindividual(i.e.(t=x1&f=x2)or(t=x2&f=x1)).Thesameaccountdealswithsentenceslike(32).Althoughthepreferentialinterpretationconveysthatbothmensinganddance,thereisalsoaninterpretationwheredi erentmendodi erentthings.11(32)Twomensinganddance.9z(men(z)^jzj2^9e(e=(e1e2)^sing(e1;x1)^dance(e2;x2)^z=(x1x2)))3.3Ontheroleoftheadverb`respectively'Inthisaccount,`respectively'issimilartootheradverbsinthatitsimplyaddsrestrictionstothesemanticsoftheverbalstructurethatitadjoinsto.Itdoesnotalteritinanyway.Letustentativelyassumethatthisadverbisrepresentedasin(33).Thesentencein(34)canthusobtaintheintendedrepresentation.(33)respectively:P:x:e:(P(x)(e)^respectively(e))(preliminary)(34)TomandFredsanganddancedrespectively.9e(e=e1e2^sing(e1;x1)^dance(e2;x2)^(tf)=(x1x2))^respectively(e))Therespectivelyreadingonlyarisesif`x1x2'isinterpretedasaplurality-formingcumulation.Inthatcase,eachverbpredicatesadi erentreferent.Asbefore,thisisthe 11Therearealsodistributivereadingsforthesesentences,whichareorthogonaltothiswork,andwhichcanbemodeledintheusualwaybyapplyingadistributiontoeachverb.Forexample,inLinkeanterms:y:e:8x(xy!dance(e;x)).Notethatsuchadistributionneednotapplytotheverbdirectlygiventheexistenceofwell-wornambiguitieslikethetwentystudentsinmyclassspeaktwolanguages,wherethetotalnumberoflanguagesspokeniseithertwo(widescopereadingoftheinde nitecomplement)orunknown(narrowscopereading).FormoreonthenatureofdistributivityseeSchein(1993),Lasersohn(1995,ch.9),Schwarzschild(1996,ch.5),Link(1991),andLandman(2000,452).15 weakidentityreadingofthesharedsubjects.Letusassumethatthissentenceistruebecause[[e]]=e01te02,wherehe01;ti2I(sing)andhe02;fi2I(dance).Sincetheadverb`respectively'canaccesssurfaceorder,itcanreadilyidentifytherankingstfande01e02.Iusetherelation`'tomean`outranks',inKay'ssense.Theadverbcanthendetectthebijectionf(e01;t);(e02;f)gbyinspectingthetuplesabove(i.e.denotedbyt

18 heverbsdescribedbythepluraleventualitye)
heverbsdescribedbythepluraleventualitye).Theadverboperatesinbasicallythesamewayinsentenceslike(35).AsdiscussedinSection3.1,anindependentlymotivatedcumulativeinterpretationallowsareadingwhereTomlovesSueandFredlovesMia.(35)TomandFredloveSueandMiarespectively.9e(sing(e;tf;sm)^respectively(e))Forexample,assumingthat[[e]]=e01te02wherehe01;t;si2I(love)andhe02;f;mi2I(love),thentherankingstfandsmallowthebijectionf(t;s);(f;m)gtobeevoked.The`love'eventsdenotedbyelackanindependentlyestablishedranking,andthereforecannotenteranybijection.Onecanassumethatexistentialclosureappliestoein(35).Nowletusconsidersomenegativeexamples.Thesentence#Amansmiledrespectivelyisnotfelicitousbecausethereisonlyoneeventandoneindividualparticipant.Thisfollowsfromthefactthat`'isarelation(i.e.requiresatleasttwoentities).In(36),however,theoddnessiscausedbytheabsenceofanindependentrankingfortheentitiesdenotedbythesubjectandthepredicate.(36)(a)#Thewomensmiledrespectively.(b)#Everymansmiledrespectively.(c)?#Eachwomanreadabookrespectively.AsdiscussedinSection2.2,thesameistruefor#Thestudentssmiledrespectivelyand#Thestudentswerepleasedbytheirscoresrespectively.AsKay(1989)correctlynotes,Thethreebeststudentsreceivedthethreebestscoresrespectivelymorereadilyelicitsacontextuallydeterminedrankingandthereforecanbefelicitous.Inowturntotheadverb.Thiswordcombineswithverbalexpressionsandpredi-catestheireventualityvariable,justlikemanyotheradverbials.Thedi erenceliesinthesatisfactionconditionsintroducedby`respectively'.Putinformally,(37a)statesthat`respectively'construestwosets,XandY.SetXcontainsalltuplesdescribinganevente0,wheree0e.Here,eistheeventualitythattheadverbpredicatesand`'istheevent-mereological`part-of'relation.SetYiscomposedofallthepairsofentitiesoccupyingtwo xedpositionsnandminthetuplesofX.Finally,Ymustbeabijectionaccordingtoacontextualranking,asde nedin(37b).Arankingissimplyasetofcontextuallydeterminedrelationslike`12'.AlthoughIomitrankingsfrom(37b),IassumethattheyareestablishedalongthelinesofKay(1989,2004)andSection2.2.(37)a.[[respectively(e)]]=1i X=f:9P9e0(2I(P)&=he0;:::i&e0[[e]])g&9n

19 9m(Y=f(pn;qm):h:::;pn;:::;qm;:::i2Xg&[[B
9m(Y=f(pn;qm):h:::;pn;:::;qm;:::i2Xg&[[Bijr(Y)]])16 b.[[Bijr(Y)]]=1i :999c(==c&(f(a;b);(a;c)gY_f(a;b);(c;b)gY))Forillustration,letussupposethatthesentencein(38)istruebecausehe1;ti2I(sing)andhe2;fi2I(dance),for[[e]]=e01te02.Fromthetruthconditionsin(37)itfollowsthatX=fhe1;ti;he2;fig,andfromthesurfaceorderweextracttherankingtfande1e2.ThisyieldsthebijectionY=f(e1;t);(e2;f)g.ThesameanalysisappliestoThesetwomensinganddance,withthedi erencethattherankingisnotduetosurfaceorder.(38)TomandFredsanganddancedrespectively.9e(e=e1e2^sing(e1;x1)^dance(e2;x2)^(tf)=(x1x2)^respectively(e))Nowletusconsidercaseswithoutverbalconjunction.AsdescribedinSection3.1,acumulativequanti cationreadingofThesetwoboyslovethesetwogirlscanbeinterpretedsothathe01;b1;g2i2I(love)andhe02;b2;g1i2I(love).Byaddingthe`respectively'adverbwecanfelicitouslyobtainY=f(1;g1);(2;g2)gifthereisametalinguisticallydeterminedranking12andg1g2.Asdiscussedabove,e01ande02arenotsucientlydistinctandsalientinordertoestablishanindependentranking.Inmultiple`respectively'sen-tenceslike(39)(McCawley1998:294),thereisacumulativequanti cationreadingoftheverbwhichyieldsX=fhe1t;b;pi,he2;m;l;gig.ThisallowsoneadverbtoevokeY=f(t;b);(m;l)gandtheothertoevokeY0=f(b;p);(l;g)g.(39)(a)TomandMartharespectivelysentabombandanastylettertothepresidentandthegovernorrespectively.(b)TomandMarthasentabombandanastyletterrespectivelytothepresidentandthegovernorrespectively.Thisanalysisisalsocompatiblewith(11),repeatedhereas(40).(40)Whiletherelationshipofthepartiesremainsamicable,itisessentialthatanagree-mentbereachedastothecoststhateachpartywillrespectivelybear.First,notethatmyaccountofraisingwillensurethattheverbbearpredicatesthesubjectreferenteachpartyandtheobjectreferentthecosts.12Second,inorderforthe`respec-tively'readingtobefelicitous,theremustbeadi erenteventandadi erentcostforeachparty,andcomprehendersmustbeabletoconceptualizetherespectiverankings.ThisispossiblebecausetheeventualityehasnarrowscopeundertheeachpartyNP.Thus,foreachpartytherewillbeadi erent`bear'situationwithacertaincost.Onewaytomodeltherespectivelyreadingof(40)istoas

20 sumethattheadverb`respectively'hasaccess
sumethattheadverb`respectively'hasaccesstoallassignmentsmadetotheeventualityvariableethatitpredicates.Inthisapproach,thesetXwillcontainthetuplesformedbythevariousvaluesfortheevariableandforxandythatarerelevantfortheinterpretationoftheverbbearinthesentence.Consequently, 12SeeSection3.4andSection4formoreonrespectivelyreadingsinraisingandcontrolstructures.17 setYwillcontainpairsofcostsandparties,whichmustformabijectionforthesentencetobefelicitous,asusual,accordingtoapragmaticallydeterminedranking.Theremaybeanalternativeanalysis,however.Schein(1993)andKratzer(2003)notethatquanti erslikeeveryallowcumulativereadings(e.g.Threecopy-editorscaughteverymistakeinthemanuscriptcanhaveaninterpretationwheredi erenteditorscaughtdi erentmistakes).Arespectivelyreadinglike(40)wouldbecomeunremarkableifeachcanhavethiskindofcumulativereadingaswell.3.4Otherkindsofdependentcumulationwithrespectivelyreadings3.4.1Inter-clausaldependenciesIn(41)wehavearespectivelyreadingentangledwithraisingandcontrolstructures.Thelogicalsubjectofhelpisthematrixsubject,afactwhichisindependentfromtherespectivelyreading.(41)FredandSueseemtowanttohelpKimandMia(respectively).Anyaccountofraisingandcontrolshouldpredictthatthelogicalformofthelowerverbishelp(fs;km),regardlessoftheexistenceofarespectivelyreading.Nothingmoreneedstobesaidbecauseacumulativequanti cationinterpretationofhelp(fs;km)asdiscussedinSection3.1sucestoobtaintherespectivelyreading.IdiscussanexplicitaccountofraisingandcontrolinSection4.2inmoredetail,butitshouldbeclearthatanysuitabletheoryofraisingandcontrolwouldobtaintheintendedrepresentation.Amoreseriouschallengeisposedbycaseslike(42),notedbyananonymousreviewer.(42)Di erentnewspapersarerunningcon\rictingreports.TheGuardianandtheTele-graphreportedthatMichaelPhelpswonthesilvermedalandthegoldmedalrespec-tively.Theclause-embeddedVPconjunctionandthematrixsubjectsomehowlicensearespec-tivelyreading,eventhoughthesetwoconjunctionsareindi erentclausesanddonotinvolveraisingorcontrol.ItisnotobvioushowtheGuardianandtheTelegraphandthesilvermedalandthegoldmedalallowarespectivelyreadingsincethereisnos

21 yntacticorsemanticrelationshipbetweenthe
yntacticorsemanticrelationshipbetweentheformerandthelatter.Isuspectthatanindependentphenomenonisatworkhere,whichcreatestheillusionthattherespectivelyreadingoccursacrosstheclausebarrier.Ithaslongbeenarguedthata`left-peripheryellipsis'phenomenon(Ross,1967;Sag,1976;Neijt,1979;Hudson,1984;vanOirsouw,1987;Wilder,1994)canpartiallyomitconjunctsasillustratedin(43).13(43)(a)[DidTomcallMaryand didMiacallSue]?(b)Thedoctor[examinedMiaonTuesdayand examinedTomonFriday].(c)He[drinksco eewithmilkatbreakfastand drinks co ee withcreamintheevening]. 13ButseeLevine(2011)forstructuresandreadingswhichresistanellipticalanalysis.18 (d)Mary[talkedaboutMonetonWednesdayand talked aboutRenoironThursday].(e)Margaret[spoketoMr.WimbleonFriday,and spoke totheDeanonSaturday].f)I[gaveyourbrotheracoloringbookand gaveabrandnewbiketoyoursister].Inparticular,Sag(1976,357)andBeavers&Sag(2004)assumethatthisellipsisprocesscantargetclausalconjunctsifsmallerellipsisdomainsarenotavailableforindependentreasons.Forexample,worldknowledgecausestheparsein(44a)tobemorelikelythantheonein(44b).Thelatteryieldsastrangereadingwherethesamemendietwice.(44)(a)TwomendiedinBaghdadonTuesday,and two men diedinTikritonFridaynight.(b)TwomendiedinBaghdadonTuesday,and diedinTikritonFridaynight.Similarly,(45a)ispreferentiallyinterpretedtomeanthatthereisatotaloftwotreesbecausecutdownisa`onetime'predicate.Thise ectvanishesin(45b)becausephotographisnotaone-timepredicate.(45)(a)Twooaktreeswerecutdownbymein1986,andbymywifein1999.(b)Twooaktreeswerephotographedbymein1986,andbymywifein1999.ThelattersentenceiscompatiblewithbothanellipticalScoordinationreadingwherethereisatotaloffourtrees(like(44a))andanellipticalVPcoordinationreadingwherethereisatotaloftwotrees(like(44b)).Crucially,ellipsissometimesyieldswhatlookslikeconstituentcoordination:(46)TwomendiedinBaghdadonTuesday,and two men diedonFridaynight.Forthesereasons,itisatleastplausiblethatthesamephenomenonoccursin(42)above,andcreatestheillusionof`respectively'spanningtwodi erentclauses.Ifso,then(42)becomesunremarkable,asillustratedin(47).Thisparseyieldsallthatisneededforarespec

22 tivelyreading,viaacumulativequanti catio
tivelyreading,viaacumulativequanti cationinterpretationofbelieve(jb;e1e2).(47)TheGuardianandtheTelegraphreported[[thatMichaelPhelpswonthesilvermedal]and[ that Michael Phelps wonthegoldmedal]]respectively.Letusconsidersomeevidenceinsupportofanellipticalanalysisof(42).Ifellipsisisatworkthenitshouldbeabletolicensenon-constituentremnants,asin(44a)and(45).Thisisconsistentwith(48).(48)JohnandBillbelievethatTomgaveabooktoSueandamagazinetoMia,respec-tively.Second,if(42)isellipticalthenitfollowswithoutfurtherstipulationthattheadverbcanappeartoberealizedinahigherclausalposition,totheleftoftheconjunctionthatitissemanticallylinkedto.Thisisshownin(49),wheretheobjectcoordinatephrasethat`respectively'mustinteractwithisembeddedintheclause.19 (49)JohnandBill[respectively[believedthatSuewantedtojogandwalk]].Notethatthisalsodispensesanyadditionalassumptionsabouttheadverbbeingallowedto\roattotheleftwhilecombiningsemanticallywiththelowerconjunction.Exampleslike(50)castseriousdoubtontheadverb'sabilityto\roatoutofitsembeddedclause.(50)*IrespectivelybelievethatTimandSueloveFredandMia.Finally,ifellipsisisatworkin(42)thenitispossibletomanipulatethesentencesothatworldknowledgecanforceanellipticalSinterpretation,asin(44a)and(45a)above.Althoughsuchasentenceisnecessarilycomplexandthereforediculttoprocess,thispredictionseemstobeborneoutin(51),whichcanrefertotwodi erentcoinsbeingfound,asopposedtothesamecoinbeingfoundtwice(alessplausibleinterpretation).(51)JohnandFredclaimthatacoinwasfoundinthekitchenonMondayandintheyardonTuesdayrespectively.Iconcludethatthereisindependentevidencesupportingthehypothesisthat(41)followsasadirectpredictionofraising/control,andthat(42)followsasadirectpredictionofleft-peripheryellipsis.Thus,theserespectivelyreadingdatapointsarenotdi erentfromthecasesdiscussedsofar.Idirectthereadertothereferencesgivenaboveforaccountsofleft-peripheryellipsisphenomena.InSection4.2Iillustratehowanindependentanalysisofraising/controlcaninterfacewiththeserespectivelyreadingswithoutfurtherstipulation.3.4.2Across-the-boardunboundeddependenciesItisgenerallyassumedsincetheseminalwork

23 ofRoss(1967)thatanidentityconditionmusth
ofRoss(1967)thatanidentityconditionmustholdbetweenelementsextractedacross-the-board.Forexample,inItwasRobinwhoFredhuggedandMiakissed,itmustbethecasethatthepatientofhugandkissisthesameperson,Robin.However,Postal(1998,136,160),Kehler(2002,125),andGawron&Kehler(2003,2004)notethattherearecertain ller{gapconstructionswhichshowthatthisisnotalwaysthecase.Considertheconjunctionin(52),fromGawron&Kehler(2004,193).(52)I nallymetSusan,Lyn,andMaryyesterday.TheyarethethreesistersxywthatBobhired x,Johnpromoted y,andBill red w.Thereisaninterpretation{possiblythemostprominentone{wherethepatientsof`hire',`promote',and` re'arethesame(strictidentity),andoneinterpretationwheretheyarenot(weakidentity).Thelatterreadingcanbemademoreprominentbyadding`respectively'.Asbefore,Irepresentbothreadingsof(52)via`',tomeanthatxandyareeitheridenticalorcumulateintoaplurality.In(53)Io ermoreexamplesof ller{gapconstructionswithcomparableinterpreta-tions.14Someofthesesentences,suchas(53b,c,d),allowthepresenceof`respectively'andthereforecorrespondtowhathasbeencalledarespectivelyreading. 14Munn(1998,1999)arguesthatexampleslike(53a)donotviolatethestrictidentityconditionim-posedbycoordination.Instead,hearguesthattheseshouldbeanalyzedasfunctionalreadings(wherepair{listreadingsareavarietyoffunctionalreading),viaspecialdoubly-indexedfunctionaltraces.SeeGawron&Kehler(2003)forseveraltechnicalandempiricalproblemsinMunn'sanalysis.20 (53)(a)Whatxydid[Kim[eat xanddrink y]]?(b)Settingasideillegalpoachingforamoment,howmanysharksxydoyouestimate[[ xdiednaturally]and[ ywerekilledrecreationally]]?(c)The[shipsxythat[[aU-boatdestroyed x]and[aKamikazeplaneblewup y]]]]weretheLaconiaandtheCallaghan.(d)Thehousesxythat[[the rereducedtoash x]and[the\roodleveleddown y]]wereneareachother.Postal(1998,136)andKehler(2002,125)alsonotedatalike(54),whichPostalclas-si esasaninterwovendependency.Iviewthesecasesasfallinginthesamecategoryas(53).AllofthesecasesfollowfromtheSharedDependentConditionforConjunctionproposedin(24).Basically,anyshareddependentiscombinedby`',evenifextracted.(54)(a)[[Whichpilot]xand[whichsailor]y]xywi

24 llJoaninvite xandGretaentertain yrespect
llJoaninvite xandGretaentertain yrespectively?(b)[[Whatbook]xand[whatmagazine]y]xydidJohnbuy xandBillread yre-spectively?(c)[[Howmanyfrogs]xand[howmanytoads]y]xydidGregcapture xandLucilletrain yrespectively?Thesameappliestoshareddependentsthatarerealizedtotherightoftheircanon-icalpositions,asincertainRight-NodeRaising(RNR)constructions.Vergnaud(1974),Abbott(1976),Jackendo (1977),Gazdar(1981,180),Postal(1998,136,178)andothersnotedcasesofadditiveRNRlike(55).(55)(a)FredspentandMialost[atotalof$10,000].(b)JohndefeatedandMarylostto[verydi erentopponents].(c)GregcapturedandLucilletrained[312frogsbetweenthem].(d)JohnhummedandMarysang[thesametune](e)Iknowamanwholostandyouknowawomanwhospent[atotalof$10,000betweenthem].Sentenceslike(55a)haveatleasttwokindsofreading:oneinwhichFredspentandMialostthesameamountofmoney(atotalof$10,000),oronewherethesumoftheamountslostandspentis$10,000.Thismaybemodeledby`',asbefore.Sinceverydi erentopponentsin(55b)denotesaplurality,itforcesthesummationinterpretation.Conversely,thesametunein(55d)forcesthestrictidentityreading.Theadverb`respectively'isnotfelicitousinthesecasesbecausetheRight-Node-Raisedconstituentdoesnotprovideanexplicitranking.Comparewith(58)below.ThesemanticsofadditiveRNRissimilartothecumulativereadingsin ller{gapdependenciesin(52){(54).Inbothcasestheshareddependentsarecombinedintoauniqueandsemanticallyricherdependent.Carlson(1987)andSabbagh(2007)assume21 thatsuchreadingsonlyarisewithrelational/symmetricpredicates,butexampleslike(55a)suggestthatthisisnotalwaysthecase.Notethattheadditivereadingin(55a)isstillavailableevenifatotalofisomitted,althoughitisnotthepreferentialinterpretation.Othercasessuchas(56)providefurtherevidencethatadditiveRNRdoesnotrequirerelational/symmetricpredicates,andcaninprinciplearisewithanypluralNPinasuitablecontext.(56)TomrelocatedtoLondon,andSuespenthersummerinParis.Ican'timaginewhyTomwouldmovetoandSuewouldvacationin[twoofthemostexpensivecitiesinEurope].TherearetwokindsofevidencesuggestingthatadditiveRNRisduetotheShared-dependentconditionforConjunction.Likerespectivelyreadings,additiveRNRreading

25 sonlyoccurinplurality-formingconjunction
sonlyoccurinplurality-formingconjunctionstructures.Hence,thedisjunctionin(57),basedonBeavers&Sag(2004,66),onlyhasanon-additivereading.Theadditivereadingre-appearswithandinsteadofeither...or.(57)EitherFredspentorMialost[$10,000].(=`EitherFredspent$10,000orMialost$10,000.')Second,liketheleftwardextractioncasesin(54),additiveRNRallowsrespectivelyreadings.Thisisshownby(58),fromPostal(1998,136,178),Gawron&Kehler(2003)andAbels(2004),respectively.ThesereadingsshouldfollownaturallyifRNRaisedde-pendentsareallowedtobecumulatedby`'justlikeanyotherdependent.(58)(a)ErnestsoldcocaineandGeorgesoldheroin[tothe rstnurseandtotheseconddentalassistant]respectively.(b)IboughttravelguidesforParisandLondonyesterday.MaryvacationedandBilldecidedtolive[inthesetwocities]respectively.(c)MaryvacationedandBilldecidedtolive[inthetwomostexpensivecitiesinEurope]respectively.3.4.3AdnominaldependenciesAnotherconstructionwhicharguablyalsoexhibitscumulationofshareddependentphrasesisillustratedin(59).Suchdatawere rstnotedbyRoss&Perlmutter(1970),Hintikka(1974),andMcCawley(1998,771).(59)(a)Amanxenteredtheroomandawomanywentout[whowerequitesimilar]xy.(b)Amanxenteredandawomanyleft[whohadmetinVienna]xy.(c)*Amanenteredorawomanleftwhowerequitesimilar.Here,arelativeclauseissimultaneouslylinkedtothesubjectsoftheprecedingconjoinedclauses.Likealltheothercasesdiscussedsofar,suchreadingsarenotpossiblewithlogicaldisjunctionandinvolveashareddependentthatisinterpretedcumulatively.22 Ifshareddependentcumulationisresponsibleforbothsplit{antecedentrelativeclausereadingsandrespectivelyreadingsthenonewouldexpectthemtobeabletoco-occurinthesamestructure,allthingsbeingequal.Thispredictionisborneoutin(60).(60)AmanenteredtheroomandawomanleftwhowereDutchandGreek,respectively.Somethingsimilarhappenswhenadnominaladjectivalphrasesconjoin,andsharethenominalheadthattheyselect.Theconjunctionofsingularadjectivescanyieldanadjec-tivalphrasecapableofmodifyingapluralnominal.Thiswasalreadyseenintheattesteddatapointin(13b)above,whichIrepeathereas(61).(61)Weknowhousesfourand vearetheSwedeandtheGerman,butwhichiswhich?Thisphenomenoni

26 snotobviousinEnglishbecauseofthelackofnu
snotobviousinEnglishbecauseofthelackofnumberagreement,butitcanbemorereadilyobservedinlanguageswhichrequireadjectivesandnounstoagreeinnumberovertly.Considerforexample(62)and(63),fromEuropeanPortuguese,wheretheconjunctionoftwosingularadjectivesyieldsaphrasethatcanadjointoapluralnominal.Ingeneral,itisnotpossibleforasingularadjectivetocombinewithanominalwithoutnumberagreement(e.g.*oschaspreto).(62)Oschaspretoeverdes~aoobtidosdathe.plteas.plblack.sgandgreen.sgare.plobtained.plfrommesmaplantasameplant`Theblackandgreenteasareobtainedfromthesameplant.'(63)OCarloseoManuelforamrespectivamenteossegundotheCarlosandtheManuelwererespectivelythe.plsecond.sgequartoclassi cadosandfourth.sgranked-participants.pl`CarlosandManuelcameinsecondandthirdplacerespectively.'ThesedataareconsistentwiththeSharedDependentConditionforConjunction.Sincethetwoconjoinedadjectivalsselectanominaldependent,thelattershouldbesharedvia`'.Thepluraleventualityformedbytheconjunctionofadjectivalpredicatesyieldsapluralitythatrespectivelycanexploitintheusualway.15Furtherexamplesofthispatternarein(64).(64)(a)Theaveragelifespanwasbetween[[zeroandone][yearsold]].(b)Kowaldiscoveredthe[[13thand14th][moonsofJupiter]].(c)Ireadthe[[secondandthird][chaptersofyourbook]].(d)Theproductionofcarbonandnitrogenwillpeakon[days[sixandseven]]. 15Forexample,inhewassimultaneouslyhappyandtired.SeealsoLasersohn(1995).23 (e)BartandLisaare[players[threeandfour]].Sentence(64a),forexample,showsthatbyconjoiningonewithzerooneobtainsaphrasethatcannowcombinewithapluralnoun.Thiscontrastswith*oneyearsold,whichisungrammaticalbecauseonemustcombinewithsingularnouns.Eachconjunctispred-icatingadi erentday,andhenceseemstoinvolveshareddependentcumulation.Asisexpected,theadverb`respectively'canbefelicitouslyadded,e.g.:(65)Theproductionofcarbonandnitrogenwillpeakondayssixandseven,respectively.Inconclusion,awiderangeofphenomenasuggeststhatshareddependentscanbesemanticallycombinedviasummation,andthatthismechanismcanyieldso-calledre-spectivelyinterpretationsasaspecialcase,whichcanbeforcedbytheovertrealizationofthe`respectively'adverb,incasether

27 eisapragmaticallyavailableranking.4AHead
eisapragmaticallyavailableranking.4AHead-DrivenPhraseStructureGrammaraccountPostal(1998,160{163)andGawron&Kehler(2004,194,195)arguethatrespectivelyphenomenaposefoundationalproblemsforcurrenttheoriesofgrammar,especiallyforuni cation-basedtheorieslikeHead-DrivenPhraseStructureGrammar(HPSG;Pollard&Sag1994).However,theaccountproposedabovesuggeststhatthesefoundationalproblemshavebeenoverstated.InwhatfollowsIshowthatHPSGcanmodeltherelevantphenomenawithoutanymajorchangestohowsubcategorizationandpredicationareusuallylexicallycoupled.Iwill,however,revisehowsubject{verbagreementisenforced.Allelsewillfollowfromthegrammarofcoordination.InSection4.1IpresentthebasicfoundationsofHPSGasoutlinedintheconstruction-basedapproachinSag(2010a,b),andinSection4.2Ishowhowthegrammarfragmentscalesuptorespectivelyphenomena.Thecumulativequanti cationphenomenadiscussedinSection3.1aredealtwithatthelevelofsemanticinterpretationandthereforewillnotbediscussedhere.4.1BasicsHead-DrivenPhraseStructureGrammarisatheoryofgrammarwherephonology,syntax,semantics,andpragmaticsco-existlocallyinthesamekindoflinguisticstructure,calledasign.Centraltothisnon-derivationaltheoryisthenotionofconstraintsatisfaction(Carpenter,1992).Thegrammarrulesarenothingmorethandeclarativestatementsthatimposeconstraintsaboutlinguisticstructure,ratherthanoperationsthatalter,compare,ordisplacepreviouslyassembledrepresentations.Theinformationconveyedbyasignisencodedassetsoffeatures.Thefeaturephonencodesphonology,synencodesvariouskindsofsyntacticinformation(includingpart-of-speech,agreement,case,andsubcatego-rizationconstraints),andsemcontainssemanticrepresentations.Signscanbeoftypewordorphrase.ThesignforthepropernameTimisgivenin(66).24 (66)2666666666666666664wordphon/tIm/syn264catnounvalhislashfg375sem266664indexx264numsgper3genmas375restrhtim=xi3777753777777777777777775Valencyisrecordedinalist-valuedfeatureval,whichinthiscaseisempty(i.e.hi).Theemptysetvalueforslashmeansthattherearenoextracteddependents.Semanticsisrepresentedasalistofrestrictionsrestrcontainingpredications.ForexpositionpurposesIadoptthe`\rat'semanticformalismo

28 fCopestakeetal.(2005)andignorethetreatme
fCopestakeetal.(2005)andignorethetreatmentofquanti erscope,butnothinghingesonthis.16FromnowonIusethesymbol`NP'asashorthandforafeaturestructuredescriptionofanominalsignwithanemptyvalencelist,asin(67).Hence,NPxisnothingbutanominalsignthathasemptyvalenceandareferentialindexx.(67)NPxisashorthandfor26664syn"catnounvalhi#semhindexxi37775Lexicalentriesandgrammarrulesarepartialdescriptionsoflinguisticstructure.Forexample,theverbsin(68)requireavalentwithnominalpart-of-speech,emptyvalence,andareferentialindex,butsaynothingaboutthephonologyorsemanticrepresentationofthatvalent.(68)(a)266666666666664wordphon/lEft/syn26664catverbvform niteval\nNPx slashfg37775semindexerestrh9eleave(e;x)i377777777777775 16InCopestakeetal.(2005)eachpredicationislabeled,andsemanticstructureisdeterminedincremen-tallyandmonotonicallybyhowthelabelsarerelated.Iomitsuchlabelsforforexpositionpurposesonly.SeealsoGinzburg&Sag(2000);Frank&Reyle(1995);Richter&Sailer(1999)andSag(2010b).25 (b)2666666666666666664wordphon/lIvz/syn266666664cat2664verbvform niteper3numsg3775val\nNPx slashfg377777775semindexerestrh9eleave(e;x)i3777777777777777775Anysignthatsatis esthesestatedconstraintswilldo.DrawingsomeinspirationfromKathol(1999),Iassumethatverbalmorpho-syntacticagreementinformationisappropri-ateforthetypeverb.Hence,theverbformin(68a)isunderspeci edandcancombinewithanykindofsubject(e.g./You/He/Theyleft),whereas(68b)canonlycombinewiththirdpersonsingularsubjects.Thetwooccurrencesofxindicatethatthetwoindicesmustbeuni ed.Inotherwords,thevariablecontributedbythesubjectNPisexactlythesameasthevariablepredicatedbytheverb;thetwoareinextricablyidenti edinthelexicalentryin(68).Ingeneral,variablebindingisensuredlexicallyinHPSG:predicatesdirectlylinktheirlogicalargumentstothevariablesoftheirvalents.Thisisoneoftheaspectsofuni cation-basedgrammarthatGawron&Kehler(2004)identifyasproblematicforrespectivelyreadings.Everythinginthegrammarisuniformlyrepresentedwithfeatures,andsyntactictreesarenoexception.ThisisshowninFigure4.Thefeaturemtrencodesinformationaboutthemothernodeandthelist-valuedfeaturedtrsencodesinformation

29 aboutthedaughtersoftheconstruction.Iuset
aboutthedaughtersoftheconstruction.Iusethetreenotationwhentalkingaboutstructureslicensedbythegrammar,andreservethefeaturematrixnotationwhentalkingaboutthegrammar.S NPVPisashorthandformtrSdtrshNP,VPiFigure4:AfeaturestructurerepresentationofatreeAs(69)shows,VPisshorthandforaverbalsignthatseeksanNP,andanSisshorthandforaverbalsignwithemptyvalence.(69)a.VPebaseisashorthandfor26666664syn2664cat"verbvformbase#valhNPi3775semhindexei3777777526 b.Sefiniteisashorthandfor26666664syn2664cat"verbvform nite#valhi3775semhindexei37777775Allgrammarrulesareoftheform),whereisatypeandisasetoffeaturesthatanyentityofthetypemustsatisfy.Theserulescancapturevaryingdegreesofgeneralizationbecausetheyarehierarchicallyorganized.Anypieceoflinguisticinforma-tionofagiventypemustnotonlysatisfyanyruleoftheform),butalsoeveryrule0)0,where0isa(directorindirect)supertypeof.Forexample,considerthetypehierarchyofphrasalrulesinFigure5.Theconstructions(cxt)inthisfragmentarephrasal,andcanbeeitherheadedornon-headed.Iviewcoordinatestructures(andperhapscertaincomparatives)asanon-headedconstructions,butnothinghingesonthisasfarasthisworkisconcerned.phrasal-cxtheaded-cxt speci er-head-cxt ... ... head-comps-cxt ... non-headed-cxt coord-cxt ... Figure5:TopnodesofthehierarchyofphrasalconstructionsFornow,letusfocusontherulesgoverningheadedconstructions,i.e.thetypessub-sumedbyheaded-cxtinFigure5.Thehead-comps-cxttypeinFigure5modelsphrasesformedbyalexicalheadanditscomplements,andthespeci er-head-cxtmodelsstruc-turesformedbyaspeci erandahead.Otherruleswillmodeladjunctionconstructions,andsoon.Thefeaturehd-dtr,whichisonlyappropriateforheadedconstructions,isusedtoidentifywhichofthedaughtersisthehead.Throughout,IuseX,Y,asvariablesoverfeaturestructuresandLasavariableoverlistsoffeaturestructures.Thespeci er-head-cxtconstructionruleallowsaheadphrasetocombinewithaspeci er,asseenin(70).(70)Speci er-HeadConstructionspeci er-head-cxt)26666664mtrsynhvalhiidtrs*X,Z:synhvalhXii+hd-dtrZ37777775ThenotationX:meansthatthevariableXdescribesafeaturestructurewithatleastasmuchinformationasthefeaturestructuredescripti

30 on.Notethat(70)issilentaboutsemantics,p
on.Notethat(70)issilentaboutsemantics,part-of-speech,orphonology.Thisrulesimplyimposes(partial)syntactic27 constraintsonalocaltree,bystatingthataconstructionofthetypespeci er-head-cxtcanbeformedbyasignXandaheadthatselectsXasavalent.Theresultingmothernodehasemptyvalence(i.e.[valhi]),liketheoneshownaboveinFigure4.FollowingMalouf(2000)andSag(2010a),Iassumethatthetypespeci er-head-cxthasvarioussubtypes,eachcapturingspeci cgrammaticalpatternsfordi erentspeci er{headconstructions.Forexample,Malouf(2000,15)modelsdi erentcaseassignmentpatternsforgerundclauseswiththreedi erentsubtypesofspeci er-head-cxt:anaccusativesubjectruledealswithclauseslike(71),apossessivesubjectruledealswith(72),andanominativesubjectruledealswithcaseslike(73).(71)(a)Patdisapprovedof[[me][quietlyleavingbeforeanyonenoticed]].(b)Everyonewasimpressedby[[Pat][artfullyfoldingthenapkins]].(72)(a)Patdisapprovedof[[my][quietlyleavingbeforeanyonenoticed]].(b)Everyonewasimpressedby[[Pat's][artfullyfoldingthenapkins]].(73)(a)[[He][wearsatuxedo]].(b)Iinsistthat[[Sandy][leavemealone]].(c)[[Pat][artfullyfoldedthenapkins]].Thereareatleastfourotherkindsofspeci er{headconstructionthathavetheirpe-culiarsyntactic,semantic,pragmatic,andprosodicconditions.First,wehave`Madmag-azine'sentences(Akmajian,1984),suchas(74),whichhaveanumberofidiosyncraticpropertiesthatcanbenaturallycapturedconstructionally(e.g.theycannotbeembed-ded,theirsubjectmustbeaccusative,andthetheyneverincludetense,modals,andsententialadverbials).(74)(a)[[Him][wearatuxedo]?!(Sure.)(b)[[Myboss][givemearaise]]?!(Ha.)(c)What![[Larry][beadoctor]]?Second,wehaveabsoluteconstructionslike(75),whichalsodi erfrom(71)inseveralways:theprepositionwithisrequired,doesnothaveanNPdistribution,adjoinstoaclause,andhasvariablesemanticconnectivitywiththematrix.SeeStump(1985);Culicover&Jackendo (2005)fordiscussion.(75)With[[him][organizingthings]],we'llnevergetanythingdone.Third,structureslike(76)appeartobeakindofspeci er{headfragmentconstructionwithanaccusativesubject.(76)Tom:I'dliketoseethatmovie.Kim:[[Me][too]].28 Finally,directiveandimperativesentenceslike(77)allow

31 optionalnon- rstpersonsubjects(butareonl
optionalnon- rstpersonsubjects(butareonlycompatiblewithsecondpersonre\rexiveobjects),andcomewithspecialpragmaticsandintonation.(77)(a)[[You][leavemealone]]!(b)[[Everyone][seatyourselves/*themselves]]!Theabovesubtypesofspeci er-head-cxtcanbemodeledbythehierarchyinFigure6.Eachtypecanintroduceparticularsyntactic,semantic,pragmaticandprosodiccon-straints.Forexample,nom-subject-pred-cxtcorrespondstotherulein(78)below,whichlicensesstructuresformedwithanominativesubjectphraseandanagreeing niteverbalheadphrase.Sincenom-subject-pred-cxisasubtypeofspeci er-head-cxt,itinheritsallitsconstraints:thespeci ersignisrequiredtobetheonlymemberofthehead'sval,andthemother'svallistisempty.speci er-head-cxtnom-subj-pred-cxt acc-subj-pred-cxt ... mad-magaz-pred-cxt Figure6:Hierarchyofspeci er{headconstructions(extendinghierarchyinFigure5).DepartingfromPollard&Sag(1994)Iproposethatsubject{verbagreementiscom-putedatthephrasallevelratherthanlexically,asshownin(78),similarlytoSag,Wasow&Bender(2003:102).(78)NominativeSubjectPredicateConstructionnom-subject-pred-cxt)26666664dtrs*2666664syncathcasenomisem24indexperXnumY3537777752664syn2664cat264vform nperXnumY37537753775+37777775Basically,thisruleensuresthatwhateveristheagreementinformationXintheVPdaugh-ter,itmustunifywiththeinformationinthenominativesubjectdaughter.AHeadedConstructionrulediscussedbelowwillensurethattheagreementspeci cationstheverb'scatarepercolatedtoitsphrasalprojections.Finally,theCoordinationConstructionruleinSection4.2willrequirethattheconjunctsandthemotherhavethesamecatvalue,andtherefore,verbalconjunctsshallimposethesameagreementspeci cationsontheirshareddependents.AlthoughtheheadedconstructionsinFigure5aredi erent,theyalsohavesimilaritieswhichcanbecapturedbythehead-cxtsupertype.Forexample,theHeadedConstructionrulein(79)ensuresthatforanyheadedconstructionthesyninformationoftheheaddaughterandofthemotherarethesame,bydefault(seeGinzburg&Sag2000:33).The29 defaultconstraint`='ensuresthatthefeaturesXoftheheaddaughterandofitsmotherareidentical,exceptifexplicitlycontradictedbytheapplicationofotherrules.Thus,(70)doesnotal

32 lowtheheaddaughterandthemothertohavethes
lowtheheaddaughterandthemothertohavethesamevalinformationinspeci er{headconstructions,butdoesallowthemtohavethesamepart-of-speech.Thus,aVPprojectsanS,anN0projectsanNP,andsoon.17(79)HeadedConstructionheaded-cxt)"mtrrsyn/Xhd-dtrrsyn/X#SomerulesareevenmoregeneralandapplytoallphrasalconstructionsinFigure5,notjusttoheadedconstructions.Oneexampleisthesemanticcompositionrulein(80),whichstatesthatthesemanticcontentofthemotherofanyphrasalstructureistheconcatenationofthesemanticcontentsofthendaughters.The`'symboldenoteslistconcatenation.18(80)PrincipleofCompositionalityphrasal-cxt)264mtrhsemmrestrX1...XnidtrsDDsemmrestrX1,...,,semmrestrXnE375Thecumulativee ectofalloftheseconstraintsisshowninFigure7.Asmentionedabove,wheneverthegrammarrequirestwofeaturestohavethesamevalue,theresultisuni cation(ormoreaccurately,structure-sharing,sinceinmodel-theoreticalgrammartherearenoproceduraloperations).Inthelinguisticstructureslicensedbythegrammarconstraints,uni cationisrepresentedviamultipleoccurrencesofaboxedtag,suchasthe 1 inFigure7.Thisstatesthatthespeci er-head-cxthasidenti edthevalentsubcategorizedbytheheadwiththenon-headdaughter. 17Incertainotherconstructions,allofthesyninformationinthemotherandintheheadremainscom-patible,andthereforetheentiresynvalueissharedvia(79).Seeforexampletheadjunctionconstructionin(89).Thee ectof(79)inadjunctionconstructionsisthatmotherandheadhaveexactlythesamesyninformation.Note,however,thatnothinginthisaccounthingesontheuseofdefaults,sinceeachclassofconstructioncanspecifyhowthevalenceinformationpropagates.18InmorerecentHPSGworkthesymbol`'isusedinsteadof`',butinordertoavoidconfusionwiththeLinkeansummationoperatorIreverttothelatternotation,originallyusedinPollard&Sag(1987).Thislistconcatenationrelationcanberecastasstandardstructure-sharingconstraints(Copestakeetal.,2001).30 26666664phrasesyn24cat 2 valhislashfg35semindexerestrhtim=x;9eleave(e;x)i37777775 1 266666666666664wordsyn2664catnouncasenomvalhislashfg3775sem2664indexx"numsgper3genmas#restrhtim=xi3775377777777777775 Tim26666666664wordsyn2664cat 2 verbvform nvalh 1 islashfg3775semin

33 dexerestrh9eleave(e;x)i37777777775 left
dexerestrh9eleave(e;x)i37777777775 leftFigure7:Representationofthesentence[[Tim]NP[left]VP]SConsidernowhowcomplementationconstructionsaremodeled.Ahead{complementruleallowsanylexicalheadtocombinewithitslexicallysubcategorizedcomplements(i.e.themoreobliquevalentsX2;:::;Xn)asdeterminedby(81).(81)PredicationalHead-ComplementConstructionhead-comps-cxt)26666664mtrhsynnvalhX1iidtrs*Y:"wordsynnvalhX1;X2;:::;Xni#,X2;:::;Xn+hd-dtrY37777775Notethatnothingissaidaboutthesemanticsorpart-of-speechofthedaughtersorofthemothernode.Anywordwithanon-emptyvalencecaninstantiatetheheadYandimposetherelevantlexicallyspeci edconstraintsontheXvalents.TheHeadedConstructionin(79)interactswiththisruleandmakessurethatthemotherandtheheaddaughterYhavethesamecatinformation.FollowingPollard&Sag(1994),asubjectraisingverblikecontinuelexicallyselectsanin nitivalVPcomplementandshareswithitssubjectvalentX.Thein nitivalauxiliaryverbtoisalsoaraisingverbandthereforealsosharesthesubjectvalentwithits(baseform)VPcomplement.TheanalysisofsubjectcontrolverbslikewantissimilarinthattheverblexicallyselectsabaseformVPandshareswithitthesamesubjectindex.Thelexicalentiresfortheseverbsareshownin(82).31 (82)(a)266666666666666666666664wordphon/k@ntInju/syn2666666666664catverbvform niteval*XVPinf24synhvalhXiisemP35+slashfg3777777777775semindexerestrh9econtinue(e;P)i377777777777777777777775(b)266666666666666666666664wordphon/wAnt/syn2666666666664catverbvformbaseval*NPxVPinf24synhvalhNPxiisemP35+slashfg3777777777775semindexerestrh9ewant(e;x;P)i377777777777777777777775Semantically,wantembedsthemeaningofthecomplementVPphrase,labeledbyl1.Thetwoverbsdi erinthatcontinuedoesnotassignanysemanticroletoitssubject.Thus,thesubjectvariableofhelpin(83)isboundtothesubjectvariableofeverydominatingverbuptothematrixverbcontinue,andcumulativequanti cationcanthenapplytohelp(e;x;y)asdiscussedinSection3.1above,andyieldtheintendedrespectivelyinterpretation.(83)FredandSuecontinuetowanttohelpKimandMia(respectively).Letusnowturntohowunbounded ller{gapdependenciesaremodeledinHPSG.19Basically,certainlexicalconstraintsallowvalentstobelocatedins

34 lashratherthaninval.Thevaluesofslasharep
lashratherthaninval.ThevaluesofslasharepercolatedtothemothernodebytheHeadedConstructionin(79),sinceslashisasynfeature.Thisiswhythedependencyisunbounded,andcanbeiteratedinde nitely.Thepercolationofgapscanbeinterruptedonlybycertainconstructions,namelythosethatimposeconstraintsonthevalueofslash.Onesuchconstructionisthetopicalizationconstruction,shownin(84),inwhichsomesignXisrealizedasasisteroftheheadclausethatcontainsthecorrespondinggap. 19SeeGinzburg&Sag(2000),Levine&Hukari(2006),andSag(2010a).32 (84)Filler{HeadConstruction ller-head-cxt)26666666664mtrsynhslashYidtrs*X,Z:264syn264catverbvalhislashfXg[Y375375+hd-dtrZ37777777775Othergaps(ifany)arepercolatedtothemother,viatheremaindersetY.Thee ectofthisheadedconstructionisillustratedinthetopicalizationsentenceinFigure8.ForexpositionpurposesIabbreviatecatinformation.Se26664synvalhislashfgsemhrestrhfred=ydana=x;9ehate(e;x;y)ii37775( ller-head-cxt) 2 NPyhrestrhfred=yii FREDSe26664synvalhislashf 2 gsemhrestrhdana=x;9ehate(e;x;y)ii37775(speci er-head-cxt) 1 NPxhrestrhdana=xii DanaVPe26664synvalh 1 islashf 2 gsemhrestrh9ehate(e;x;y)ii37775 hatesFigure8:Atopicalizationconstruction.4.2ConjunctionandrespectivelyFortheanalysisofverbalcoordinationIassumeafamiliarbinarybranchingrulelikeX!XX,whichIformalizeinHPSGtermsas(85),drawingfromBeavers&Sag(2004).IleaveopenthepossibilityofrevisingthisruleasproposedinSag(2002)inordertogeneralizetoothercategories,andtodealwithcoordinationof`unlikecategories'phenomena.20 20Whereasnominalcoordinationmustallowagreementmismatchese.g.Tomandus,verbalcoordinationmustnot:twoverbalconjunctsmustbearstrictlyconsistentagreementinformationincat.However,other33 (85)VerbalCoordinationConstructionv-coord-cxt)2666664mtrsynhcatX:verbidtrs*24synhcatXicrd{3524synhcatXicrdcrd-marked35+3777775Thisconstructionallowstwoverbalconstituentstobecoordinatedaslongastheyhavecompatiblecatvaluesand rstdaughterisnotmarkedwithacoordinator(i.e.bearsthespeci cation[crd]),andtheseconddaughterismarkedwithacoordinator(i.e.bears[crdcrd-marked]).Iassumethatthecrd-markedtypehasseveralsubtypes,oneforeachkindofcoordinationmar

35 ker.Thus,thelexicalentryforandislexicall
ker.Thus,thelexicalentryforandislexicallyspeci edas[crdconj],theentryfordisjunctionorislexicallyspeci edas[crddisj],andsoon.Sincethemothernodein(85)isunderspeci edforthevalueofcrd,thisrulecanapplyrecursivelyasintended.Therearevarioustypesofcoordination,oftenwithspecialsyntactic,prosodic,semanticandpragmaticcharacteristics.Togivesomewell-knownexamples,considerpackagingconjunction(e.g.Eggs,cheeseandbaconwasallIneeded),numeralconjunction(e.g.counted vehundredandtwenty-twocats),arithmeticalconjunction(e.g.Twoandtwoisfour),conditionalconjunction(e.g.TakeonemorestepandI'llshootyouwhereyoustand),andintensi cationconjunction(e.g.Thesoundbecamelouderandlouder),amongotherslikeBooleanconjunction,andplurality-formingnon-Booleanconjunction(TomandMaryagreed,Youcan'tsimultaneouslydrinkanddrive,Kimrarelysingsanddances,orRobinreadthenewspaperanddriedherhairinexactlytwentyseconds).Theseandothercoordinationpatternscanbemodeledwithatypehierarchyofconstructionsinwhicheachtypeintroducesthespeci cconstraintsassociatedwiththatkindofcoordination.InthisworkIfocusonnon-Booleanconjunction,andontheformalizationoftheSharedDependentConditionforConjunction.InordertodescribesumindicesinHPSG,Iview`'asthefunctionde nedin(86).(86)(x;y)=zi [[z]]=([[x]]t[[y]])Plurality-formingconjunctionmustcreateapluralityfromthedenotationofthecon-juncts.Thisisdonebytakingtheindices 1and 2oftheconjunctsandcombiningthemvia`'.Similarly,thereferentsofeverysignselectedbytheconjunctsmustbecombinedvia`'.Thisisformalizedin(87),whichgeneralizestoanynumbermofshareddependents.21 verbalcatinformationneednotmatch,suchasaux:Kimlikebagelsandhecaneatalotofthem.SeeSag(2002).21TheLinkeansum`'conditionscanalternativelybeinsertedinrestrviathefeaturec(onstructional)-cont(ent)fromCopestakeetal.(2005)(cf.withChaves(2009)).Therulein(87)iscompatiblewiththetheoryofextractionproposedinGinzburg&Sag(2000),butnotwiththeoneadvocatedinChaves(2012b).Inordertomakeitso,(87)wouldberevisedasfollows.Themother'sslashvalueisinsteadde nedasX1[X2,whereX1istheslashvalueofthe rstcon-junctandX2ofthesecond.The[relationcorrespondstoasymmetricaland

36 non-deterministicsetunionoperationwith`
non-deterministicsetunionoperationwith`'combination.Thisisde nedintermsofthreeconditions.Thebasecaseis34 (87)Non-BooleanConjunction(m0)nbool-cnj-cxt)266666666666666666666666664mtr2666664syn264valDXP(x0;y0)0,...,XP(xn;yn)nEslashnXP(xn+1;yn+1)n+1,...,XP(xm;ym)mo375semhindex( 1; 2)i3777775dtrs*26664synvalhXPx00;...,XPxnnislashfXPxn+1n+1;...,XPxmmgsemhindex 1i3777526664synvalhXPy00;...,XPynnislashfXPyn+1n+1;...,XPymmgsemhindex 2i37775+377777777777777777777777775InthisworkIfocusontheinstancesofv-coord-cxtwhicharealsosubtypesofnbool-cnj-cxt.Obviously,otherkindsofverbalcoordinationdonotformaplurality(e.g.BooleancoordinationslikeItisnotraininganditisnotsnowingordisjunctionslikeIcansingordance).ThecurrentgrammarthuslicensesstructuresliketheoneinFigure9,withthesemantics9z(men(z)^z=(x1x2)^sing(e1;x1)^dance(e2;x2)).Ifx1x2isinterpretedasequalitythenx1=x2andthereforethemenarebothsinginganddancing.However,ifx1x2isinterpretedasasumthenx1=x2andweobtainareadingwherethemensinginganddancingaredi erent.Thisinterpretationisconsistentwiththeadverb`respectively'.Sevalhirestrh9zmen(z);9e1sing(e1;x1);9e2dance(e2;x2)i(speci er-head-cxt) 1 NPzhrestrh9zmen(z)ii ThemenVPe=(e1;e2)valh 1 NPz=(x1;x2)irestrh9e1sing(e1;x1);9e2dance(e2;x2)i(nbool-cnj-cxt) VPe1valhNPx1irestrh9e1sing(e1;x1)i sangVPe2valhNPx2irestrh9e2dance(e2;x2)i anddancedFigure9:Valentsharinginconjunction:`Themensanganddanced'. fg[X=X,thesetunioncaseis(f g[X1)[(f g[X2)=f ; g[(X1[X2),andthe`'caseis(f g[X1)[(f g[X2)=f  g[(X1[X2).35 WhereasGawron&Kehler's(2004)accountobtainsthesereadingsfromdi erentsyntactictreesanddi erentsemanticrepresentations,thepresentaccountdoesnot.Infact,bothstrictandweakidentityreadingsaretheresultofasingletreestructureandasinglesemanticrepresentation.Asentencelike(88)ismodeledinthesameway,theonlydi erencebeingthatthesubjectisani-sumratherthanaplural.(88)SueandKarensinganddance.z=(y1y2)^sue=y1^karen=y2^z=(x1x2)^sing(e1;x1)^dance(e2;x2)Thiscanbeinterpretedwithorwithoutarespectivelyreadingbecauseof`'.Moreover,ifzisapluralitythenbythesymmetryof`'itfollowsthateithery1=x1andy2=x2,ortha

37 ty1=x2andy2=x1.Instancesofrespectivelyre
ty1=x2andy2=x1.Instancesofrespectivelyreadingsinvolving ller{gapdependencieslike`whichbookandwhatmagazinedidyousaythatJohnboughtandBillread'andothersdiscussedinSection3.4.2arecapturedinaverysimilarway,asshowninFigure10.Theonlydi erenceisthatthedependentsthataresharedandsummedareextractedsignsratherthansignsinsitu.Forsimplicity,Iomitthesemanticrepresentationbutitshouldbeclearthattheverbsboughtandreadpredicatex1andx2respectively,andthatthetwovariablesarecombinedvia`'attheconjunctionnode.ThesignsinslashpercolateinthetreeasaconsequenceoftheHeadedConstruction.Exactlyasbefore,if`'isinterpretedasequalitythenz=(x1=x2),butifitisinterpretedasplurality-formingcumulationthenzisapluralityformedwithx1andx2.Foranaccountofinterrogativeandsubject{auxiliaryinversionconstructionsseeGinzburg&Sag(2000)andSag(2010b).Theadverb`respectively'operatesessentiallylikeanyotherverbalmodi er,syntacti-callyandsemantically.Thefeaturesel(ect)allowsmodi ers,determinersandmarkerstolexicallyimposeconstraintsontheheadsthattheycombinewith.Suchstructuresaremodeledviathehead-functor-cxtruleprovidedin(89).22Sincethisruledoesnotim-poseanyconstraintsonthemothernode,theHeadedConstructionwillforceallthesyntacticfeaturesoftheheadandthemothertobeidentical.(89)Head{FunctorConstructionhead-functor-cxt)26664dtrs*X,24syn"selhXivalhi#35+hd-dtrX37775Thelexicalentryfor`respectively'isprovidedin(90),andconsistsofanadverbthatselectsaverbalheadviaselandpredicatestheverbevent. 22Asinalloftheconstructionsinthiswork,theorderoftheelementsindtrsisnotimportant.Asmentionedabove,alinearizationtheoryliketheoneofPollard&Sag(1987)orKathol(2000)determineswhichorderingsarepossibleinphon.36 Se3valhislashfg 1 NPz whatbookandwhatmagazineSe3valhislashf 1 g Ve3264inv+valh 3 , 4 islashf 1 g375 did 3 NP you 4 VPe3valh 3 islashf 1 g Ve3valh 3 , 2 islashf 1 g say 2 Se=(e1;e2)24valhislashD 1 NPz=(x1;x2)E35 Se1valhislashfnpx1g JohnboughtSe2valhislashfnpx2g andBillreadFigure10:Gapsharinginanacross-the-boardextractionconstruction.(90)26666666666666666666664wordphon/รด@spEktIvlI/syn266666666664cat266664adverbsel*264synhcatverbisemhindex

38 ei375+377775valhislashfg377777777775semi
ei375+377775valhislashfg377777777775semindexerestrhrespectively(e)i37777777777777777777775Notethatsincenoconstraintsareimposedonval,theverbalheadcanbeaverbphraseorasentence,coordinateornot.Figure11illustrateshow(90)and(89)interact.Iomitsomefeaturesforexpositionpurposes.TheadverbisinterpretedasinSection3.3.Ifwerevisetheconjunctionrulein(87)sothatthesigninselthatconjunctsshareiscombinedvia`'thenweobtainanN0liketheonein(91)andtherespectivesemantic37 VPe 1 VPeAdvPe2664syncathselh 1 iisemhrestrhrespectively(e)ii3775Figure11:Genericexampleofadverbialadjunction.representation.TheanalysisisshowninFigure12,andisparalleltowhathappenstoshareddependentsrecordedinvalandslashasdiscussedabove.(91)Theeventwilltakeplacebetween[dayssixandseven]N0.days(z)^9s1order(s1;x1)=6^9s2order(s2;x2)=7^s=s1s2^z=x1x2Basically,whenadjunctsareconjoinedanysignselectedviaseliscombinedviathe`'relation.Itistrivialtorevisetheconjunctionrulein(87)toachievethise ectonselvalues.N0zhrestrhdays(z);9s1order(s1;x1)=6;9s2order(s2;x2)=7ii(head-functor-cxt) 1 N0zhrestrhdays(z)ii daysAPs=(s1;s2)24cathselh 1 N0z=(x1;x2)iirestrh9s1order(s1;x1)=6;9s2order(s2;x2)=7i35(nbool-cnj-cxt) APs124cathselhN0x1iirestrh9s1order(s1;x1)=6i35 sixAPs224cathselhN0x2iirestrh9s2order(s2;x2)=7i35 andsevenFigure12:Conjunctionofadnominalexpressions.AsimilarapproachcanbeadoptedforshareddependentcumulationinRNRandinsplit{antecedentrelativeclauseextraposition,asdiscussedinSection3.4.2.ThereareseveralalternativeanalysesofRNRandExtraposition,whichIcannotdiscussbecauseofspacelimitations(butseeChaves2012a).MygoalhereistosuggestthatRight-Node-Raisedshareddependentsarealsosubjecttotheshareddependentcumulationphe-nomenon:anysignsselectedasdependentsbyeachoftheconjunctsarecombinedvia`',38 asshown,fortheexamplein(55a)above,inFigure13.If`'isinterpretedasequalitythenweobtainstandardnon-additiveRNR(thestrictidentityreading,wherethetotalofmoneyunderdiscussionis$20,000).If`'isinterpretedasplurality-formingcumulationthenweobtaintheadditiveRNRcases(theweakidentityreading,wherethetotalofmoneyis$10,000).IsuspectthattherearevariouskindsofRN

39 Rconstruction,andthatthekindillustratedb
Rconstruction,andthatthekindillustratedbelowisessentiallyacross-the-boardrightwardextraction,alongthelinesofGazdar(1981);seealsoChaves(2011).Theadverb`respectively'canadjointothecoordinateSeandevokeabijectionasusual,providedthatthereisarankingestablishedbysurfaceorder.InthecaseofFigure13nosuchrankingispossibleandthereforethepresenceof`respectively'isnotfelicitous.Ifarankingcanbeestablished,however,weobtaincaseslike(58)above.Se Se=(e1;e2) Se1 Fredspent x1Se2 andMialost x2NPz=(x1;x2) atotalof$10,000Figure13:Right-NodeRaising5ConclusionThispaperhasarguedthatrespectivelyreadingsaretheconsequenceoftwoindepen-dentlymotivatedphenomenaandthattheroleoftheadverb`respectively'isnottoalterpreviouslyassembledsemanticstructures,butrather,toaddconstraintsonthesemanticsoftheadjoinedphrase.TheadverbisbestviewedasacontextualoperatorinthesenseofKay(1989),whosefunctionistosingleoutone-to-onemappingsaccordingtoanindepen-dentlyestablishedcontextualranking.Accesstosuchrankingsisalsoavailabletootherexpressionsliketheformer,thelatterandinthatorder.Ihaveproposedthattwocom-pletelydistinctandindependentlymotivatedphenomenacanyieldcertaininterpretationswhicharecompatiblewiththepresenceoftheadverb`respectively'.Somerespectivelyreadingsfollowfromaphenomenonusuallycalledcumulativequanti cation(Scha,1981),andothersarisefromconjunctscumulatingtheirshareddependents.ThegeneralizationunderlingthelattercasesisencapsulatedbytheSubjectDependentConditionforCon-junction,whichstatesthatthei-sumoperationindependentlyproposedbyLink(1983)tomodelnon-Booleanconjunctionisalsorelevantformodelinghowdependentssharedbyconjunctsaresemanticallyintegrated.Inthisview,respectivelyreadingsarebutspecialcasesofawiderrangeofindependentlymotivatedinterpretations.AsfarasIamaware,thisistheonlyanalysisintheliteraturewhichexplainswhyrespectivelyreadingscanarisewithouttheovertrealizationoftheadverb.39 Theproposedanalysisismoreparsimoniousthanitspredecessorsintwocrucialways.First,sentenceshavethesamesyntacticandsemanticstructureregardlessoftherespec-tivelyreading.Second,thereisnoneedforaradicaldecouplingbetweensubcategori

40 zationandpredication.Predicatescandirect
zationandpredication.Predicatescandirectlypredicatethereferentsofthedependentsthattheyselect.Thisisachievedwithoutresortingtonon-monotonicoperationsthatdisruptthetightconnectionbetweensyntaxandsemantics,andextendstocomplexcasesthatinvolve ller{gapdependencies,extraposition,adjunction,andRight-NodeRaising.Asaconsequence,respectivelyreadingscanbestraightforwardlymodeledbyuni cation-basedgrammarwithoutthefoundationalproblemsraisedbyPostal(1998)andGawron&Kehler(2004).Finally,thisaccountcanmodelcertainrespectivelyreadingsinvolvingsingularNPs,whichpreviousaccountspredicttobeungrammatical.ReferencesAbbott,Barbara.1976.RightNodeRaisingasaTestforConstituenthood.LinguisticInquiry7,639{642.Abels,Klaus.2004.Rightnoderaising:ellipsisoracrosstheboardmovement?InKeirMoultonandMatthewWolf(eds.),Nels34:proceedingsofthirty-fourthannualmeetingoftheNorthEastLinguisticSociety,pages45{60,BooksurgePublishing,Charleston,US.Akmajian,Adrian.1984.SentenceTypesandtheForm-FunctionFit.NaturalLanguage&LinguisticTheory2(1),1{23.Alshawi,HiyanandCrouch,Richard.1992.MonotonicSemanticInterpretation.InPro-ceedingsofthe30thACL,pages32{39,Newark,NJ.Asher,NicholasandLascarides,Alex.2003.LogicsofConversation.CambridgeUniversityPress.Bach,Emmon.1986.Thealgebraofevents.LinguisticsandPhilosophy9,5{16.Bach,Emmon,Brown,C.andMarlsen-Wilson,W.1986.CrossedandnesteddependenciesinGermanandDutch:apsycholinguisticstudy.LanguageandCognitiveProcesses(1),249{262.Barker,Chris.2007.Parasiticscope.LinguisticsandPhilosophy30(4),407{444.Bartsch,Renate.1973.Thesemanticsandsyntaxofnumberandnumbers.InJohnP.Kimball(ed.),SyntaxandSemantics.Vol2,pages51{93,NewYork:AcademicPress.Beavers,JohnandSag,IvanA.2004.EllipsisandApparentNon-ConstituentCoordi-nation.InStefanMuller(ed.),Proceedingsofthe11thInternationalConferenceonHead-DrivenPhraseStructureGrammar,KatholiekeUniversiteitLeuven,pages48{69,Stanford:CSLIPublications.Beck,SigridandSauerland,Uli.2000.Cumulativityisneeded:areplytoWinter(2000).NaturalLanguageSemantics8,349{371.Carlson,GregN.1987.SameandDi erent:SomeConsequencesforSyntaxandSemantics.LinguisticsandPhilosophy10,

41 531{565.40 Carpenter,Bob.1992.TheLogicof
531{565.40 Carpenter,Bob.1992.TheLogicofTypedFeatureStructures.CambridgeUniversityPress.Chaves,RuiP.2009.Construction-basedCumulationandAdjunctExtraction.InProceed-ingsofthe16thInternationalConferenceonHead-DrivenPhraseStructureGrammar,UniversityofGottingen,Germany,pages47{67,Stanford:CSLIPublications.Chaves,RuiP.2011.ExtrapositionandAdditiveRightNodeRaising,paperpresentedatthe18thInternationalConferenceonHead-DrivenPhraseStructureGrammar.Chaves,RuiP.2012a.OnthedisunityofRightNodeRaisingphenomena:Extraposition,Anaphora,andEllipsis,unpublishedmanuscript.UniversityatBu alo.Chaves,RuiP.2012b.Onthegrammarofextractionandcoordination,NaturalLanguageandLinguisticTheory.DOI:10.1007/s11049-011-9164-y.Chomsky,Noam.1972.Someempiricalissuesinthetheoryoftransformationalgram-mar.InStanleyPeters(ed.),Goalsoflinguistictheory,EnglewoodCli s,NewJersey,Prentice-Hall.Copestake,Ann,Flickinger,Daniel,Sag,IvanA.andPollard,Carl.2005.MinimalRecur-sionSemantics:AnIntroduction.JournalResearchonLanguage&Computation3(4),281{332.Copestake,Ann,Lascarides,AlexandFlickinger,Dan.2001.AnAlgebraforSemanticConstructioninConstraint-basedGrammars.InProceedingsofthe39thACL,Toulouse,France.Culicover,PeterandJackendo ,RayS.2005.SimplerSyntax.OxfordUniversityPress.Dalrymple,Mary.1999.SemanticsandsyntaxinLexicalFunctionalGrammar:There-sourcelogicapproach.Cambridge.MA:MITPress.Dalrymple,Mary&AndrewKehler.1995.OntheConstraintsImposedbyRespectively.LinguisticInquiry26(3),531{536.vanEijck,Jan.1983.Discourserepresentationtheoryandplurality.InA.G.B.terMeulen(ed.),StudiesinModel-theoreticSemantics,pages85{106,Foris,Dordrecht.Fast,Jakub.2005.Structurallyunderspeci edsemanticsfordistributivepluralpredica-tion-RespectivelyconstructionsinLexicalResourceSemantics.InSylviaBlaho,LuisVicenteandErikSchoorlemmer(eds.),ProceedingsofConSOLEXIII.Fodor,JanetDean.1978.Parsingstrategiesandconstraintsontransformations.LinguisticInquiry9,427{473.Frank,AnetteandReyle,Uwe.1995.Principle-basedSemanticsforHPSG.InProceedingsofthe6thMeetingoftheAssociationforComputationalLinguistics,EuropeanChapter,Dublin.Gawron,JeanM.andKehler,

42 Andrew.2004.TheSemanticsofRespectiveRead
Andrew.2004.TheSemanticsofRespectiveReadings,ConjunctionandFiller{GapDependencies.LinguisticsandPhilosophy27,169{207.Gawron,JeanMarkandKehler,Andrew.2003.RespectiveAnswerstoCoordinatedQues-tions.InSemanticsandLinguisticTheory13(SALT13),UniversityofWashington,Seattle,Washington.Gazdar,Gerald.1981.UnboundedDependenciesandCoordinateStructure.LinguisticInquiry12(2),155{184.41 Gazdar,Gerald,Klein,Ewan,Pullum,Geo reyK.andSag,IvanA.1985.GeneralizedPhraseStructureGrammar.Oxford:Blackwell,andCambridge,Ma:HarvardUniver-sityPress.Ginzburg,JonathanandSag,IvanA.2000.InterrogativeInvestigations:theform,mean-inganduseofEnglishinterrogativeconstructions.Stanford:CSLIPublications.Goodall,Grant.1987.ParallelStructuresinSyntax:Coordination,Causatives,andRe-structuring.NewYork:CambridgeUniversityPress.Halvorsen,Per-Kristian.1988.SituationSemanticsandSemanticInterpretationinConstraint-BasedGrammars.InProceedingsoftheInternationalConferenceonFifthGenerationComputerSystems,pages471{478,Tokyo,Japan,reprintedasFormalIs-suesinLexical-FunctionalGrammar1995(eds.)MaryDalrymple,RonaldKaplan,JohnT.MaxwellIII,andAnnieZaenen,pp.293{309.Stanford:CSLIPublications.Higginbotham,James.1985.OnSemantics.LinguisticInquiry16,547{593.Hintikka,Jaakko.1974.Quanti ersvs.quanti cation.InDialectica,27,pages329{358,Also:LinguisticInquiry5(1974),pp.153{177.Hoeksema,Jack.1988.Thesemanticsofnon-Booleanand.JournalofSemantics6,16{40.Hudson,Richard.1984.WordGrammar.Blackwell.Jackendo ,Ray.1977. X-Syntax:AstudyofPhraseStructure.theMITPress.Kamp,Hans.1979.Events,InstantsandTemporalReference.InA.vonStechowR.Bauerle,U.Egli(ed.),Semanticsfromdi erentpointsofview,pages376{417,Springer-Verlag,Berlin.Kathol,Andreas.1999.AgreementandtheSyntax{MorphologyInterfaceinHPSG.InRobertD.LevineandGeorgiaGreen(eds.),StudiesinContemporaryPhraseStructureGrammar,pages209{260,CambridgeandNewYork:CambridgeUniversityPress.Kathol,Andreas.2000.LinearSyntax.OxfordUniversityPress.Kay,Paul.1989.Contextualoperators:respective,respectively,andviceversa.InKiraHall,MichaelMeachamandRichardShapiro(eds.),TheProceedingsoftheFifteenthAnnualMeeting

43 oftheBerkeleyLinguisticsSociety,pages181
oftheBerkeleyLinguisticsSociety,pages181{192,Berkeley,CA:BerkeleyLinguisticsSociety,Inc.Kay,Paul.2004.PragmaticAspectsofGrammaticalConstructions.InLaurenceHornandGregoryWard(eds.),TheHandbookofPragmatics,pages675{700,Blackwell.Keenan,EdwardL.1992.BeyondtheFregeboundary.LinguisticsandPhilosophy15,199{221.Kehler,Andrew.2002.Coherence,Reference,andtheTheoryofGrammar.Stanford:CSLIPublications.Kratzer,Angelika.2003.Theeventargumentandthesemanticsofverbs,Ms.UniversityofMassachusettsatAmherst.Krifka,Manfred.1989.NominalreferenzundZeitkonstitution.ZurSemantikvonMassen-termen,PluraltermenundAspektklassen.Fink,Munchen.Krifka,Manfred.1989.Nominalreference,temporalconstitution,andquanti cationin42 eventsemantics.InRenateBartsch,JohanvanBenthem,andPetervanEmdeBoas(eds.),SemanticsandConceptualExpressions,Dordrecht:Foris.Krifka,Manfred.1990.Booleanandnon-Boolean`and'.InLaszloKalmanandLaszloPols(eds.),PapersfromthesecondsymposiumonLogicandLanguage,pages161{187,AkademiaiKiado,Budapest.Kroch,Anthony.1974.TheSemanticsofScopeinEnglish.Ph.D.thesis,MITDissertation.Landman,Fred.2000.EventsandPlurality:theJerusalemLectures.Dordrecht:KluwerAcademicPublishers.Lasersohn,Peter.1995.Plurality,ConjunctionandEvents.Kluwer:Dordrecht.Levine,RobertD.2011.Linearizationanditsdiscontents,presentedatthe18thInterna-tionalConferenceonHPSG,Seattle,Washington.USA.Levine,RobertD.andHukari,ThomasE.2006.TheUnityOfUnboundedDependencyConstructions.CSLIPublications.Link,Godehard.1983.Thelogicalanalysisofpluralsandmassterms:alattice-theoreticalapproach.InR.Bauerle,C.SchwarzeandA.vonStechow(eds.),Meaning,UseandInterpretationofLanguage,pages302{323,Berlin:deGruyter.Link,Godehard.1991.Plural.InA.vonStechowandD.Wunderlich(eds.),Semantics:AnInternationalHandbookofContemporaryResearch,pages418{440,DeGruyter,Berlin.Link,Godehard.1998.AlgebraicSemanticsinLanguageandPhilosophy.Stanford,CA:CSLIPublications.Malouf,Robert.2000.MixedCategoriesintheHierarchicalLexicon.Stanford:CSLIPub-lications.McCawley,JamesD.1968.TheRoleofSemanticsinaGrammar.InE.BachandR.T.Harms(eds.),UniversalsofLinguisticTheory,pages124{169

44 ,NewYork:Holt,Rein-hart,andWinston.McCaw
,NewYork:Holt,Rein-hart,andWinston.McCawley,JamesD.1998.TheSyntacticPhenomenaofEnglish.Chicago:UniversityofChicagoPress,secondedition.Moltmann,Friederike.1992.CoordinationandComparatives.Phd.dissertation,MIT:Cambridge,Massachusetts.Munn,Alan.1998.ATBmovementwithoutidentity.InJenniferAustinandAaronLawson(eds.),Proceedingsofthethe14thEasternStatesConferenceonLinguistics(ESCOL-97),pages150{160,CSCPublications.Munn,Alan.1999.OntheidentityrequirementofATBextraction.NaturalLanguageSemantics7,421{425.Neijt,Anneke.1979.Gapping.Foris,Dordrecht.vanOirsouw,RobertR.1987.ThesyntaxofCoordination.London:CroomHelm.Parsons,Terence.1990.EventsinthesemanticsofEnglish:Astudyinsubatomicseman-tics.Cambridge,MA:MITPress.Partee,Barabara.1984.NominalandTemporalAnaphora.LinguisticsandPhilosophy7(3),243{286.43 Pollard,CarlandSag,IvanA.1987.Information-BasedSyntaxandSemantics,vol1:fundamentals.Stanford,CA:CSLIPublications.Pollard,CarlandSag,IvanA.1994.Head-DrivenPhraseStructureGrammar.Chicago:UniversityofChicagoPressandStanford:CSLI.Postal,PaulM.1998.Threeinvestigationsofextraction.MIT:Cambridge,Massachusetts.Pullum,Geo reyK.andGazdar,Gerald.1982.Naturallanguagesandcontext-freelan-guages.LinguisticsandPhilosophy4,471{504.Pustejovsky,James.1991.Thesyntaxofeventstructure.Cognition41,47{81.Richter,FrankandSailer,Manfred.1999.Underspeci edSemanticsinHPSG.InHarryBuntandReinhardMuskens(eds.),ComputingMeaning,StudiesinLinguisticsandPhilosophy,pages95{112,Kluweracademicpublishers.Roberts,Craige.1987.ModalSubordination,AnaphoraandDistributivity.PhD.thesis,UniversityofMassachusettsatAmherst.Ross,JohnR.1967.ConstraintsonVariablesinSyntax.Doctoraldissertation,MIT,Cambridge,Massachusetts.[Publishedin1986asIn niteSyntax!Norwood,NJ:AblexPublishing].Ross,JohnR.andPerlmutter,D.M.1970.RelativeClausesWithSplitAntecedents.LinguisticInquiry1,350.Sabbagh,James.2007.OrderingandLinearizingRightwardMovement.NaturalLanguageandLinguisticTheory25(2),349{401.Sag,IvanA.1976.DeletionandLogicalForm.PhD.Dissertation,MIT,publishedin1980byNewYork:GarlandPress.Sag,IvanA.2002.CoordinationandUnderspeci cation.InProceedin

45 gsofthe9thInterna-tionalConferenceonHead
gsofthe9thInterna-tionalConferenceonHead-DrivenPhraseStructureGrammar,KyungHeeUniversity,Seoul,SouthKorea,pages267{291,Stanford,CSLIPublications.Sag,IvanA.2010a.EnglishFiller{Gapconstructions.Language86(3),486{545.Sag,IvanA.2010b.Sign-BasedConstructionGrammar:Aninformalsynop-sis,Ms.,StanfordUniversity.ToappearinHansC.BoasandIvansA.Sag(eds.),Sign-BasedConstructionGrammar.Stanford:CSLIPublications.[http://lingo.stanford.edu/sag/papers/theo-syno.pdf,accessed16February2012].Sag,IvanA.,Wasow,ThomasandBender,EmilyM.2003.SyntacticTheory-Aformalintroduction.2ndEdition.Stanford:CSLIPublications.Scha,Remko.1981.Distributive,CollectiveandCumulativeQuanti cation.InJeroenA.G.Groenendijk,TheoM.V.JanssenandMartinJ.B.Stokhof(eds.),FormalMethodsintheStudyofLanguage,pages483{512,Amsterdam:MathematicalCenterTracts.Schein,Barry.1993.PluralsandEvents.Cambridge,Mass.:MITPress.Schwarzschild,Roger.1990.AgainstGroups.InMartinJ.B.StokhofandLeenTorenvliet(eds.),ProceedingsoftheSeventhAmsterdamColloquium,pages475{494,(Amsterdam:ILLC,UniversityofAmsterdam,1989).Schwarzschild,Roger.1996.Pluralities.Dordrecht:Kluwer.44 Shieber,StuartM.1988.Auniformarchitectureforparsingandgeneration.InProceedingsofthe12thconferenceonComputationallinguistics-Volume2,COLING'88,pages614{619,Stroudsburg,PA,USA:AssociationforComputationalLinguistics.Shieber,StuartM.andSchabes,Yves.1992.GenerationandSynchronousTree-AdjoiningGrammars.ComputationalIntelligence7(4),220{228.Steedman,Mark.1996.SurfaceStructureandInterpretation.MITPress.Steedman,Mark.2001.TheSyntacticProcess.MITPress.Sternefeld,Wolfgang.1998.ReciprocityandCumulativePredication.NaturalLanguageSemantics6,303{337.Stockwell,RobertP.,Schachter,PaulandPartee,Barbara.1973.TheMajorSyntacticStructuresofEnglish.NewYork:Holt,Rinehart,andWinston.Stump,GregoryT.1985.TheSemanticVariabilityofAbsoluteConstructions.Dordrecht:Reidel.Vergnaud,Jean-Roger.1974.FrenchRelativeClauses.Doctoraldissertation,MIT,Cam-bridgeMassassuchets.Wilder,Chris.1994.Coordination,ATBandellipsis.InJ.-WZwart(ed.),MinimalismandKayne'sAntisymetryHypothesis,pages291{331,UniversityofGroningen.4

Related Contents


Next Show more