/
Actuality and Knowability David J Actuality and Knowability David J

Actuality and Knowability David J - PDF document

conchita-marotz
conchita-marotz . @conchita-marotz
Follow
360 views
Uploaded On 2015-01-28

Actuality and Knowability David J - PPT Presentation

Chalmers It is widely believed that for all or at least for all entertainable it is knowable a priori that actually It is even more widely believed that for all such it is knowable that actually There is a simple argument against th ID: 34515

Chalmers widely

Share:

Link:

Embed:

Download Presentation from below link

Download Pdf The PPT/PDF document "Actuality and Knowability David J" is the property of its rightful owner. Permission is granted to download and print the materials on this web site for personal, non-commercial use only, and to display it on your personal computer provided you do not modify the materials and that you retain all copyright notices contained in the materials. By downloading content from our website, you accept the terms of this agreement.


Presentation Transcript

Premises(2)and(3)appeartobeinstancesofcoreprinciplesofthelogicsgoverningKandA:Ap!Apand(Kp!p).PerhapsonecandenythattheEnglishword`actually'satises(2),butitishardtodenythatthereisatechnicaltermthatworksthisway.Denying(3)appearstorequireallowingthattherecanbeknowledgeoffalsepropositions(althoughmoreonthislater).Premise(4)followsfromtwoprinciplesgoverningentertaining:entertainingapropositionrequiresentertainingitsconstituents,andknowingapropositionrequiresentertainingthatpropo-sition.Ifristrue,sothatno-oneentertainsq,thentherstprincipleentailsthatno-oneen-tertainsr$Ar(ofwhichqisaconstituent),andthesecondprinciplethenentailsthatno-oneknowsr$Ar.Someonemightobjecttotheseprinciplesbyholdingthatknowledgeisdisposi-tionalwhileentertainingisoccurrent,orthatentertainingisnotasubpropositionalnotion.Onecanstraightforwardlygetaroundtheseworriesbyreinterpreting`Ep'as`Someoneentertainsapropositionofwhichpisaproperorimproperconstituent',andreinterpreting`Kp'as`Someoneoccurrentlyknowsp',or`Someoneknowspwhileentertainingp'.TheconclusionfollowsfromthepremisesbyclassicallogicandtheweakmodallogicK(infact,byminimallogicandbytheversionofKonwhichtheoremsofminimallogicarenecessary).From(3)and(4),onecanderive(K(r$Ar)!((r$Ar)&:r)).From(1)and(2),onecanderive(K(r$Ar)!Ar).Fromthesetwoclaimsonecanderive(K(r$Ar)!(r&:r)),fromwhichtheconclusionfollows.Theoriginalversionoftheconclusionisthenegationofaninstanceofthekeythesisthatforallp,itisknowablethatp$Ap.Evenifwemakethemodicationsabove,themodiedconclusionthatitisnotoccurrentlyknowablebyhumansthatr$Arisnolessinteresting,asthestandardreasonsforholdingthatitisknowableapriorithatp$Aparealsoreasonsforholdingthatitisoccurrentlyknowablebyhumansthatp$Ap(atleastwhenthepropositionisentertainablebyhumans).Itisworthnotingthattherearealsoversionsoftheargumentthatdonotrelyonthenotionsofconstituencyorofentertaining.Theargumentrequiresonlyatruepropositionrthatsatises(4):thatis,suchthatrnecessitates:K(r$Ar).Forexample,ifonerejectsthenotionofconstituencybecauseonetakespropositionstobesetsofpossibleworlds,onecansimplytakertobeanytrueproposition(apairofworldsincludingtheactualworldandoneother,forexample)suchthat:Krholdsinallr-worlds.ThenassumingthatAristhenecessaryproposition,rwillsatisfy(4),andtheconclusionfollows.Anotherversionoftheargument,relevantforsomeonewhoacceptsconstituencybuthasdoubtsaboutentertaining,takes`Eq'tomean`Someoneknows(p$Ap)forsomepofwhich2 Giventhesurprisingconsequences,onemaywanttoexaminetheoptionsforrespondingtotheargumentinmoredetail.Anumberoftheavailableoptionsaretiedtodi erentavailableviewsofthesemanticsof`actually'andofthewayitbehavesinepistemicandmodalcontexts.Whatwemightcalltheface-valueviewof`actually'holdsthatthereisapropositionexpressedby`Ap'suchthat`KAp'and`Ap'aretruei thispropositionisknownornecessary(andlikewiseforother`A'-involvingsentences).Giventheface-valueview,theconclusion(5)followsdirectlyfromthestandardprinciplesabove(Ap!Ap,therecanbenoknowledgeoffalsepropositions)andtheexistenceofatruepropositionthatsatises(4).AparticularlyclearillustrationisprovidedbytheRussellianface-valueview,whichcombinestheface-valueviewwiththeclaimsthat`p'expressesaRussellianpropositionpandthat`Ap'expressestheRussellianpropositionp(@)holdingthatpistrueintheactualworld-state@.3IfristheRussellianproposition:Eq,whereqisaRussellianpropositionthatisnotactuallyentertained,thenitiseasytoseethatiftheRussellianpropositionr$r(@)isentertainedinaworld,itisfalseinthatworld.Sothepropositioncannotbe(occurrently)known,andgiventheface-valueview,(5)follows.TheRussellianface-valueviewallowsadiagnosisofthesurprisingconsequencesabove.Ifthisviewiscorrect,itispossibletousethesentence`r$Ar'toexpressknowledge.Wemightsaythatsomeoneknowsasentencewhentheyknowthepropositionitexpressesintheworldofknowledge(perhapsaspresentedundertheguiseofthesentence).Inthissense,itispossibletoknow`r$Ar'.Butifonedidso,inapossibleworldw,thesentencewouldexpressapropositionr$r(w)distinctfromthepropositionr$r(@)thatitactuallyexpresses.Onemightsaythatthesentence`r$Ar'issemanticallyfragile:thepropositionitexpressesdependsonwhetherspeakersattempttoknowwhetherthesentenceistrue.4Semanticfragilityyieldsanaturalexplanationoftheunknowabilityofthepropositioninquestion:onecouldknowthesentence,butifonedid,itwouldexpressadi erentproposition(thatis,apropositiondistinctfromthepropositionitactuallyexpresses).Itcanalsoexplainthefailureofclosureofknowabilityunderlogicalentailment:onecouldusethetheentailmenttoderivethesentence`p$Ap',but sentences,butwecanextendittopropositionsbysayingthataproofofapropositionpinasystemLisanabstractsequenceofinterpretedsentencessuchthatthesequenceisaproofinL(invirtueofthelogicalformofthesentences)ofasentencethatexpressesp.3Itisnotobviousjustwhatitistoknowapropositionabouttheactualworld@inanotherpossibleworld.Williamson(1987)raisesquestionsaboutthisnotioninrespondingtoEdgington(1985),whoinvokesthenotioninaddressingFitch'sparadoxofknowability.Soames(2007)givesanaccountonwhichsuchknowledgeinvolvesasortofcompletedescriptivespecicationof@.4 @inthisway.Ifoneweretoundergotheprocessonewoulddemonstratenot@butadi erentworld-statew.Onemighttherebycometoknowthepropositionp$p(w)apriori,butonewouldnottherebycometoknowthepropositionp$p(@)apriori.SoSoames'argumentfails.Assumingthatthisprocessistheonlywaytocometoknowsuchpropositionsapriori(whenpisnotitselfknowableapriori),thenthenaturalconclusionisthat(forsuchp),theRussellianpropositionp$p(@)isknowableapriorii itisknownapriori.SemanticfragilityisnotlimitedtoaRussellianviewofpropositions.Ifoneholdsanobject-involvingFregeanview,onwhichthepropositionexpressedbyasentenceisaFregeanpropositionwiththereferentsofsimpleexpressionsinthesentenceasconstituents,onewillalsobeconfrontedwiththeissueofsemanticfragility.Ifthisviewiscombinedwiththeviewthattheactualworld-stateispartoftheextensionof`actually',thensentencessuchas`r$Ar'willbesemanticallyfragile,justasontheRussellianview.Ifthisviewiscombinedwithaface-valuesemanticsfor`actually',thenitwillyieldconsequencesanalogoustothoseoftheRussellianface-valueview.6Ofcourse,thefactthatsemanticfragilityprovidesadiagnosisofthesurprisingconsequencesneednotmakethoseconsequenceseasiertoaccept.Onemightstillwanttoholdthatp$Apisalwaysknowableapriori,oratleastthatitisalwaysknowable.Todoso,oneneedsanalternativeviewofthesemanticsof`actually'.Oneclassofalternativeviewsholdsthatthesentencesinquestionarenotsemanticallyfragile,sothat`r$Ar'expressesthesamepropositioninallworlds.Forexample,onemightholdthat`actually'isaprimitiveoperator,orthatthesentencesinquestionexpresstheirprimaryintensions,orthat`Ap'expressesthesamepropositionas`p'.Buttoavoidtheconsequences,onewillstillbeleftwithadicultchoicebetweendenying(2)anddenying(3),andgiventhestandardprinciplesmentionedabove,onewillstillbeleftdenyingtheface-valueview.7Thenaturalupshotisthattoavoidtheconclusion,rejectingsemanticfragilityislessimportantthanrejectingtheface-valueview. 6Allthisappliestotheobject-involvingFregeanviewinChalmers(forthcoming),onwhichsentencesexpressenrichedpropositions:structuredtwo-dimensionalentitiesinvolvingbothprimaryintensionsandextensionsascon-stituents.Giventhat`r$Ar'expressesanenrichedpropositionwiththeactualworld@asaconstituentandgivenface-valuesemanticsformodalandepistemiccontexts,(5)follows.Topreservestandardtwo-dimensionalclaimsabouttheapriorityof`p$Ap'(e.g.DaviesandHumberstone1980),oneneedstoinvokenotionsofsententialandpropo-sitionalaprioritythatcomeapartfromaprioriknowabilityofaproposition(seeChalmersforthcoming,notes24and25).7Aviewthatrejectssemanticfragilityandholdsthatthesentence`Ap$p'isalwaystruewhenutteredwillprobablyholdthatthatApistrueataworldi pistruethere,andwillalmostcertainlyholdthisbiconditionalacross6 thatthereisathirdreadingof`actually'—perhapsthecanonicalphilosophicalreading–onwhich(2)istrueand(5)isfalse,sothat(3)isfalsealso.Iamsympathetictothepluralistviewmyself,butevenonthepluralistview,theexistenceofareadingof`actually'onwhichtheargumentissoundisenoughtoraisemanyoftheoriginalissues.Forexample,therearguablyremainsanintuitionthatforallp,thepropositionexpressedby`pi inthisveryworld-statep'istrivial,knowable,andknowableapriori.Ifso,thereremainsthequestionofhowtoreconcilethisintuitionwiththeargumentagainstit.Analternativewayofrespondingtotheargumentistoacceptitsconclusionwhileholdingontoaversionoftheoriginalthesisthatp$Apisalwaysknowable,byarguingthatthereisasenseof“knowable”inwhichapropositionmaybeknowableeventhoughitisnotmetaphysicallypossiblethatitbeknown.Oneversionofthisstrategyappealstoagentivepossibility(whatispossibleforanagent,wherethismightbeunderstoodassomethinginthevicinityofwhattheagenthasthecapacitytodo),holdingthatapropositionisknowablewhenitisagentivelypossibleforsomeonetoknowit,whiledenyingthatagentivepossibilityentailsmetaphysicalpossibility.9Thispositionfacesanobviouschallenge,however,inthattheoriginalargumentmightbereformulatedintermsofagentivepossibility,andthecaseforthefourkeypremisesremainsstrongwhentheyarereadthisway.Anotherattempttondadi erentsenseof“knowable”isinspiredbythetwosensesof“prov-able”discussedearlier.Accordingtothisproposal,apropositionisknowable(apriori)i thereexistsaconclusive(apriori)justicationforit.Itwouldtakesomeworktomakethisproposalprecise,butanaturalthoughtisthatajusticationisroughlyanalogoustoaproof:anabstractstructureofpropositionsandevidence,standinginrelationsofsupport,groundedinevidenceoratleastinknownorjustiedpropositions.Onecouldthensaythatanapriorijusticationisonegroundedonlyinnon-experientialevidenceorinpropositionsthatareknown/justiedapriori,andaconclusivejusticationisajusticationappropriateforknowledge.Ine ect,thisanalysisyieldsnonmodalnotionsofjustiability,knowability,andaprioritythataredistinctfromthemorefamiliarmodalnotions,andthatareinsteadanalogoustothestandard 9Fara(2010)developsastrategyofthissortinrespondingtoFitch'sparadox.Inasimilarspirit,onemightalsousetheproposalinthenextparagraphtorespondtoFitch'sparadox.OnecouldconsistentlyholdthatthereexistsaconclusivejusticationfortheFitchpropositionp&:Kp,invirtueofthereexistingseparateconclusivejusticationsforpand:Kp,althoughitisimpossibletousethisjusticationtoknowtheproposition.Insofarasthisnotionyieldsanonmodalnotionofknowabilityanalogoustothestandardnonmodalnotionofprovability,itmightalsoyieldasenseinwhichtheFitchpropositionisknowable.8 Hazen,A.1978.Theeliminabilityoftheactualityoperatorinpropositionalmodallogic.NotreDameJournalofFormalLogic19:617-22.Humberstone,I.L.1982.Scopeandsubjunctivity.Philosophia12:99-126.Soames,S.2007.Actually.ProceedingsoftheAristotelianSociety,SupplementaryVolume81:251-77.Williamson,T.1987.Ontheparadoxofknowability.Mind96:256-61.10