/
Paradoxes in the School of Names Paradoxes in the School of Names

Paradoxes in the School of Names - PowerPoint Presentation

tawny-fly
tawny-fly . @tawny-fly
Follow
364 views
Uploaded On 2018-03-21

Paradoxes in the School of Names - PPT Presentation

Chris Fraser 方克濤 Associate Professor Department of Philosophy HKU PhD from HKU won the 1999 Li Ka Shing prize Author of The Philosophy of the Mozi The First Consequentialists ID: 659528

white kind names paradox kind white paradox names predicate horses dogs school proper michael semantics horse level kinds black

Share:

Link:

Embed:

Download Presentation from below link

Download Presentation The PPT/PDF document "Paradoxes in the School of Names" is the property of its rightful owner. Permission is granted to download and print the materials on this web site for personal, non-commercial use only, and to display it on your personal computer provided you do not modify the materials and that you retain all copyright notices contained in the materials. By downloading content from our website, you accept the terms of this agreement.


Presentation Transcript

Slide1

Paradoxes in the School of NamesSlide2

Chris Fraser 方克濤

Associate Professor, Department of Philosophy, HKU

PhD from HKU, won the 1999 Li

Ka Shing prizeAuthor of The Philosophy of the Mozi: The First ConsequentialistsSlide3

The School of Names

M

ing

jia 名家, Warring States (479–221 B.C.E.) thinkers who shared an interest in language, logic, and metaphysics.Not really a “school”: the individuals lived centuries apart, in different regions of China, with distinct interests.Mostly no surviving original texts.Slide4

The School of Names

Intellectuals

known as the

bian zhe 辯者 or “dialecticians.”Deng Xi 鄧析

Yin

Wen

Hui

Shi 惠施Gongsun Long 公孫龍Slide5

Mohist Dialecticians

In addition, some of the paradoxes we will be concerned with come from the

Mohist

dialecticians, who operated in the same general time period (Warring States) as the School of Names.Slide6

Identity and PredicationSlide7

The Xunzi

子3rd century philosophical work.In particular, written long after the dialecticians we’re studying.Written by a school surrounding the philosopher

Xunzi

.

Disliked paradoxes (a “great depravity”) and had a “general disdain for intellectual curiosity.”

One of few sources of info about the School of Names.Slide8

The Xunzi

子The Xunzi argues that the correct use of names “is necessary to clarify social ranks, distinguish similar from different things, communicate intentions, and carry out

tasks.”Slide9

Mohist Robber Paradox

“Disliking

there

being many robbers is not disliking there being many people.”“Desiring there be no robbers is not desiring there be no people.”

“Not-caring

about robbers is not not-caring about

people.”

“Killing robber-people

is not killing people” (

Mozi 45/16–17).Slide10

A Fallacious Argument

God is love.

Love is blind.

Ray Charles is blind.Therefore, Ray Charles is God.Slide11

IndividualsSlide12

Proper Names

A proper name picks out an individual.

MichaelSlide13

KindsSlide14

Predicates

A predicate picks out a kind of individuals.

humanSlide15

Truth Conditions: PN + PRED

A proper name + predicate sentence is true if the individual named by the proper name is in the kind named by the predicate.

Example: ‘Michael is human’ is true if

is in:Slide16

Identity vs. Predication Statements

Not every ‘is’ statement in English is a predication statement. We also have the ‘is’ of identity. Compare:

Michael is human.

Michael is the instructor of PHIL 2511.The second statement has no predicate, but two “proper names” (singular terms). Slide17

Truth Conditions: PN = PN

A proper name = proper name sentence is true if the individual named by the first proper name

is identical to

the individual named by the second proper name.Example: ‘Michael is the instructor of PHIL 2511’ is true if =Slide18

A Fallacious Argument Analyzed

God

PN

is lovePN.LovePN is

blind

PRED

.

Ray

Charles

PN is blindPRED.Therefore, Ray Charles

PN

is

God

PN

.Slide19

GodPN

is

love

PN.This is an identity statement, so it gets us: =Slide20

LovePN

is

blind

PRED.

is inSlide21

LovePN

is

blind

PRED.

is inSlide22

RayPN

is

blind

PRED.

is inSlide23

Ray

Charles

PN

is

God

PN

?Slide24

Paradox Resolved

The argument hinges on a confusion between identity statements and predicate statements.

If all the statements were identity statements, it would work:

God = Love = Blind = Ray CharlesSlide25

The White Horse ParadoxSlide26

Gongsun Long

Lived c

. 320–250 B.C.E

.He was a retainer to the Lord of Pingyuan (d. 252 B.C.E.) in the state of Zhao.Only member of the School of Names that we have texts from.Slide27

White Horse Paradox

The white horse paradox consists of several arguments for the following claim:

“White horses are not horses.”Slide28
Slide29

White Horse Paradox

Consider the following sentence:

“Michael wants horses.”

‘Michael’ is clearly a proper name, but ‘horses’ is clearly not. So it must pick out a kind.Slide30
Slide31

White Horse Paradox

Now consider this sentence:

“Michael wants white horses.”

By similar reasoning, ‘white horses’ picks out a kind.Slide32
Slide33

White Horse Paradox

The kinds picked out are different kinds. This is clear enough:

If someone seeks horses, brown or black horses can comply. If someone seeks white horses, brown or black horses cannot comply.”Slide34

Gongsun Long’s Interpretation

=Slide35

More Semantics: QuantifiersSlide36

Quantifiers

So far we’ve considered statements like:

Michael is human.

Michael is the instructor of PHIL 2511.But what about:All dogs are animals.No dogs are humans.Slide37

Quantifier Semantics

In contemporary semantics, quantifiers like ‘all’, ‘no’, and ‘some’ express relations among kinds:

All Fs are

Gs means every member of the kind F is also a member of the kind G.Some Fs are Gs means there is an individual that is in kind F and also in kind G.No Fs are

Gs

means there are no individuals that are in kind F and also in kind G.Slide38

‘All Dogs are Animals’Slide39

Bare Plurals: Four Interpretations

[ALL]: Dogs are animals.

[GEN]: Birds fly.

[SOME]: Mosquitos carry the West Nile Virus.[KIND]: Dinosaurs are extinct.Slide40

Interpretations Determined by Predicate

[ALL]: Dogs

are animals

.ALL-interpretation from individual-level predicate.[GEN]: Birds fly.GEN-interpretation from individual-level predicate.[SOME]: Mosquitos carry the West Nile Virus.

SOME-interpretation from stage-level predicate.

[KIND]: Dinosaurs

are extinct

.

KIND-interpretation from KIND-level predicate.Slide41

White Horse Paradox

‘Are horses’ is an individual-level predicate.

So ‘white horses are horses’ receives the interpretation ‘ALL white horses are horses.’Slide42
Slide43

(You can probably see how we’d handle the robber paradox too.)Slide44

Problems for Extensional Semantics: Three ParadoxesSlide45

Three Paradoxes

While the white horse paradox and the robber paradox can be resolved with the tools of modern semantics, a few other paradoxes from the school of names show the limitations of those tools.

Mountains and gorges are level. (Hui Shi)

Dogs are not hounds. (Mohists)White dogs are black. (Mohists

)Slide46

Xunzi’s World

T

he correct use of names “is necessary to clarify social ranks, distinguish similar from different things, communicate intentions, and carry out tasks.”

This assumes that there is a correct classification scheme imposed by the meanings of words.Slide47

Xunzi’s World

T

he correct use of names “is necessary to clarify social ranks, distinguish similar from different things, communicate intentions, and carry out tasks.”

This assumes that there is a correct classification scheme imposed by the meanings of words.Slide48

KindsSlide49

Mountains and gorges are level.

“By

everyday standards, mountains

and abysses or the sky and the earth are different in height, but from some sufficiently distant

standpoint or by some sufficiently vast standard, the difference between

them may

be insignificant, such that they count as level or beside each other

.”Slide50

‘Big’, ‘Small’, etc.Slide51

Relativization

The standard method of solving this sort of problem is

relativization

to a context.Remember temporal relativism: Nobody just sits or stands, you sit-at-a-time and you stand-at-a-time. So we say nothing is ever just big or small. Things are big-in-one-context and small-in-another.Slide52

One common interpretation of Hui Shi’s theses is

that… [they] attempt

to show that the similarities and differences by which we distinguish things can be identified in indefinitely many ways, depending on one’s standpoint. Apart from the standpoints we take up, there are noindependent, preexisting standards by which to identify a scheme of privileged, correct distinctions

. The world in itself fixes no particular way of drawing distinctions

as correct.”Slide53

Response 1: Natural Kinds

This idea certainly has Western parallels.

Some philosophers have said there

are natural ways of dividing up the world: “natural kinds,” or “joints of nature.” Slide54

Response 2: (Scientific) Anti-Realism

On the other hand, some philosophers have said there are no such privileged carvings, and thus things like the objects of scientific inquiry (like electrons or dark matter) only exist from our conceptual scheme: there’s no sense in which someone with a different scheme is missing important truths.Slide55

Dogs are not hounds.

“In

the

Mohist Canons, ‘dog’ and ‘hound’

(or

‘pup’

and

‘dog’)

are stock examples

of coextensive terms, of which a speaker might know one without knowing the other. A speaker unaware that the two terms are coextensive could know about dogs and yet say without error that he didn’t know about hounds (Canon B40).”Slide56

Frege’s Puzzle

This paradox shows a shortcoming in our extensional semantics.

The kind dog = the kind hound, but it seems that ‘dog’ and ‘hound’ have different meanings (cognitive significance). Slide57

Frege’s Puzzle

Frege, for example, introduced a two-tiered semantics.

Words referred to individuals and kinds, but they also had senses, and the sense of ‘dog’ and ‘hound’ were distinct.Slide58

White dogs are black.

“[I]n

determining the application of a compound

name such as “black person,” one must fix what part of a person is the criterion for

deeming the

person “black.” Presumably it is the person’s skin color, not hair color, for

example. If

one chooses an unorthodox criterion for deeming a dog black, such as the dog’s

nose, dogs

with white fur might be deemed ‘black.’”Slide59

Charles Travis, “Pragmatics”

“Pia’s Japanese maple is full of russet leaves. Believing that green is

colour

of leaves, she paints them. Returning, she reports, ‘That’s better. The leaves are green now.’ She speaks truth.A botanist friend then phones, seeking green leaves for the study of green-leaf chemistry. ‘The leaves (on my tree) are green,’ Pia says. ‘You can have those.’ But now Pia speaks falsehood.”Slide60

The Point

For Travis, we’re talking about the same leaves (individuals) and putting them in the same kind (green), but the truth-values are different.

For Frege, extensional semantics didn’t capture the whole meaning, but it did at least capture the truth-value. Travis (and the

Mohists?

) challenge this.Slide61

The Point

For Travis, we’re talking about the same leaves (individuals) and putting them in the same kind (green), but the truth-values are different.

For Frege, extensional semantics didn’t capture the whole meaning, but it did at least capture the truth-value. Travis (and the

Mohists?) challenge this.Slide62

ConclusionSlide63

Conclusion

The members of the School of Names– like

Kongzi

and Xunzi– were interested in how we use words to “carve up” the world and make distinctions.Unlike those other schools, however, the School of Names was interested in challenging ordinary or naïve assumptions that we make about the use of words.I think contemporary semantic technology can help us see both where the dialecticians went wrong and how they got it right.